Skip to main content
Log in

A Philosophical Evaluation of Adaptationism as a Heuristic Strategy

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Acta Biotheoretica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Adaptationism has prompted many a debate in philosophy of biology but the focus is usually on empirical and explanatory issues rather than methodological adaptationism (MA). Likewise, the context of evolutionary biology has provided the grounding for most discussions of the heuristic role of adaptationism. This paper extends the debate by drawing on case studies from physiology and systems biology to discuss the productive and problematic aspects of adaptationism in functional as well as evolutionary studies at different levels of biological organization. Gould and Lewontin’s Spandrels-paper famously criticized adaptationist methodology for implying a risk of generating ‘blind spots’ with respect to non-selective effects on evolution. Some have claimed that this bias can be accommodated through the testing of evolutionary hypotheses. Although this is an important aspect of overcoming the pitfalls of adaptationism, I argue that the issue of methodological biases is broader than the question of testability. I demonstrate the productivity of adaptationist heuristics but also discuss the deeper problematic aspects associated with the imperialistic tendencies of the strong account of MA.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a criticism of the analogy see Houston (2009).

  2. Distinctions between MA and EA were made earlier (Mayr 1983; Sober 1993, 1996). Godfrey-Smith’s (2001) account includes a third position called ‘explanatory adaptationism’ (ExA), whereas Lewens (2009) increases the number of types to seven. Since I shall mainly focus on MA in this paper, the distinction between MA and EA will suffice for this paper. ExA can arguably also be seen as a part of what I define as strong MA—an imperialistic account of MA that may also influence explanatory ideals in biology (Sects. 3, 4).

  3. They would, however, object to a strong form of EA that considers developmental constraints only as non-directional limitations to selection.

  4. The name originates from early speculations by whalers that the oil could be the whale’s sperm but this idea was rejected as oil was also found in females (Whitehead 2003).

  5. It is now known that the spermaceti organ is not homologous to the sound-conducting organ in dolphins (called the melon) but to the right anterior bursae in the phonic lips.

  6. For similar claims see (Alon 2007b, c; Shen-Orr et al. 2002).

  7. Reichenbach’s famous distinction between a context of discovery and of justification has been questioned since the 1970s, in particular in recent practice-oriented philosophical accounts (Schickore and Steinle (ed) 2009). These have argued that discovery and justification are both theoretically and temporally related.

  8. I have greatly benefitted from discussions with Arnon Levy and William Bechtel regarding this issue.

  9. The example is analogous to Coddington’s “Two-Horn Rhinoceros Problem” (Sober 1993, 123). Even if horns in rhinos (or phonic lips in porpoises) are clear examples of adaptations, it does not follow that selection explains why some species have two instances of the trait. Similarly, the selective advantage of some network motifs does not show that the general overabundance is due to the same evolutionary mechanism.

  10. For well-understood and simple molecular traits developing over short evolutionary time scales direct experimentation may be possible. When evolutionary experiments in vivo or in silico are possible, testing of adaptive hypotheses can be easier than for the macrolevel. This problematizes any strong distinction between the ramifications of MA with respect to organizational levels.

  11. It is however compatible with the aim of studying the effects of selection. Selective constraints can be added to the model to identify the integrated long-term effects of mutational priming and selection.

Abbreviations

EA:

Empirical adaptationism

MA:

Methodological adaptationism

References

  • Alon U (2003) Biological networks: the tinkerer as an engineer. Science 301:1866–1867

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alon U (2007a) An introduction to systems biology: design principles of biological circuits. Chapman & Hall, Boca Raton

    Google Scholar 

  • Alon U (2007b) Network motifs: theory and experimental approaches. Nat Rev Genet 8:450–481

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alon U (2007c) Simplicity in biology. La nature 446:497

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson R (1994) Two concepts of constraint: adaptationism and the challenge from developmental biology. Philos Sci 61:556–578

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Babu MM, Luscombe NM, Aravind L, Gerstein M, Teichmann SA (2004) Structure and evolution of transcriptional regulatory networks. Curr Opin Struct Biol 14:283–291

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon R, Rausher M (1996) Testing adaptationism: a comment on Orzack and Sober. Am Nat 148:189–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke M (1970) Function of the spermaceti organ of the sperm whale. Nature 228:873–874

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke M (1978) Buoyancy control as a function of the spermaceti organ in the sperm whale. J Mar Biol Assoc UK 58:27–71

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conant G, Wagner A (2003) Convergent evolution of gene circuits. Nat Genet 34:264–266

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cordero OX, Hogeweg P (2006) Feed-forward loop circuits as a side effect of genome evolution. Mol Biol Evol 23:1931–1936

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dekel E, Mangan S, Alon U (2005) Environmental selection of the feed-forward loop circuit in gene-regulation networks. Phys Biol 2:81–88

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1995) Darwin’s dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life. Penguin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Felsenstein J (1985) Phylogenies and the comparative method. Am Nat 125:1–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forber P (2009) Spandrels and a pervasive problem of evidence. Biol Philos 24:247–266

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2001) Three kinds of adaptationism. In: Orzack SH, Sober E (eds) Adaptationism and optimality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 335–357

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin B (1994) How the Leopard changed its sports. The evolution of complexity. Phoenix, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1996) The mismeasure of man. Norton and Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ, Lewontin RC (1979) The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme. Proc R Soc B 205:581–598

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (1996) The historical turn in the study of adaptation. Br J Philos Sci 47:511–532

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen T, Pienaar J, Orzack S (2008) A comparative method for studying adaptation to a randomly evolving environment. Evolution 62:1965–1977

    Google Scholar 

  • Hogeweg P (2012) Toward a theory of multilevel evolution: long-term information integration shapes the mutational landscape and enhances evolvability. In: Soyer O (ed) Evolutionary systems biology. Springer, London, pp 195–223

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Houston A (2009) San Marco and evolutionary biology. Biol Philos 24:215–230

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kimura M (1985) The neutral theory of molecular evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Knabe JF, Nehaniv CL, Schilstra MJ (2008) Do motifs reflect evolved function? No convergent evolution of genetic regulatory network subgraph topologies. BioSystems 94:68–74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight CG, Pinney JW (2009) Making the right connections; biological networks in the light of evolution. BioEssays 10:1080–1090

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konagurthy AS, Lesk AM (2008) On the origin of distribution patterns of motifs in biological networks. BMC Syst Biol 2:73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koonin EV (2011) Are there laws of genome evolution? PLoS Comput Biol 7:e1002173

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuo DP, Banzhaf W, Leier A (2006) Network topology and the evolution of dynamics in an artificial genetic regulatory network model created by whole genome duplication and divergence. BioSystems 85:177–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewens T (2004) Organisms and artifacts: design in nature and elsewhere. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewens T (2009) Seven types of adaptationism. Biol Philos 24:161–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch M (2007a) The evolution of genetic networks by non-adaptive processes. Nat Rev Genet 8:803–813

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch M (2007b) The frailty of adaptive hypotheses for the origins of organismal complexity. Proc Natl Acad Sci 104:8597–8604

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Madsen P (2002) Kaskelothvalens store næse. Aktuel Naturvidenskab 3:8–11

    Google Scholar 

  • Madsen PT, Payne R, Kristiansen NU, Wahlberg M, Kerr I, Møhl B (2002) Sperm whale sound production studied with ultrasound time/depth-recording tags. J Exp Biol 205:1899–1906

    Google Scholar 

  • Madsen PT, Wisniewska D, Beedholm K (2010) Single source sound production and dynamic beam formation in echolocating harbour porpoises (Phocoena phocoena). J Exp Biol 213:3105–3110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mangan S, Zaslaver A, Alon U (2003) The coherent feedforward loop serves as a sign-sensitive delay element in transcription networks. J Mol Biol 334:197–204

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1983) How to carry out the adaptationist program? Am Nat 121:324–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mazurie A, Bottani S, Vergassola M (2005) An evolutionary and functional assessment of regulatory network motifs. Genome Biol 6:35.1–35.12

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milo R, Shen-Orr S, Itzkovitz S, Kashtan N, Chklovskii D, Alon U (2002) Network motifs: simple building blocks of complex networks. Science 298:824–827

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Møhl B (2001) Sound transmission in the nose of the sperm whale Physeter catodon. A post mortem study. J Comp Physiol 187:335–340

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Møhl B, Madsen PT, Wahlberg M, Whitlow W, Nachtigall P, Righway S (2003) Sound transmission in the spermaceti complex of a recently expired sperm whale calf. Acoust Soc Am ARLO 4(1):19

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller G, Newman SA (2003) Origination of organismal form: beyond the gene in developmental and evolutionary biology. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen R (2009) Adaptationism: 30 years after Gould and Lewontin. Evolution 63:2487–2490

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norris KS, Harvey GW (1972) A theory for the function of the spermaceti organ of the sperm whale (Physeter catodon L.). In: Galler SR et al (eds) Animal orientation and navigation. NASA, Washington, DC, pp 397–417

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris K, Møhl B (1983) Can odontocetes debilitate prey with sound? Am Nat 122:85–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley M (2012) Evolutionary systems biology: historical and philosophical perspective on an emerging synthesis. Adv Exp Med Biol 751:1–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack S, Sober E (1994a) How (not) to test an optimality model. Trends Ecol Evol 9:265–267

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack S, Sober E (1994b) Optimality models and the test of adaptationism. Am Nat 143:361–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack S, Sober E (1996) How to formulate and test adaptationism. Am Nat 148:202–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack S, Sober E (2001) Adaptation, phylogenetic inertia, and the method of controlled comparisons. In: Orzack S, Sober E (eds) Adaptationism and optimality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 45–63

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2009) An extended synthesis for evolutionary biology. Ann NY Acad Sci 1168:218–228

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M, Kaplan J (2000) The fall and rise of Dr Pangloss: adaptationism and the spandrels paper 20 years later. Trends Ecol Evol 15:66–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Resnik D (1997) Adaptationism: hypothesis or heuristic. Biol Philos 12:39–50

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson R (2007) Evolutionary psychology as maladapted psychology. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Salvado B, Karathia H, Chimenos A, Vilaprinyo E, Omholt S, Sorribas A, Alves R (2011) Methods for and results from the study of design principles in molecular systems. Math Biosci 231:3–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schickore J, Steinle F (eds) (2009) Revisiting discovery and justification, historical and philosophical perspectives on the context distinction. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Shen-Orr S, Milo R, Mangan S, Alon U (2002) Network motifs in the transcriptional regulation network of Escherichia coli. Nat Genet 31:64–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1993) Philosophy of biology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1996) Evolution and optimality: feathers, bowling balls, and the thesis of adaptationism. Philos Exch 26:41–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Solé RV, Valverde S (2006) Are network motifs the spandrels of cellular complexity? Trends Ecol Evol 21:419–422

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steinacher A, Soyer O (2012) Evolutionary principles underlying structure and response dynamics of cellular networks. In: Soyer O (ed) Evolutionary systems biology. Springer, London, pp 225–247

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sterely K (2007) Dawkins vs. Gould, survival of the fittest. Icon Books Ltd., Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Tyson J, Novák B (2010) Functional motifs in biochemical reaction networks. Annu Rev Phys Chem 61:219–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward JJ, Thorton JM (2007) Evolutionary models for formation of network motifs and modularity in the Saccharomyces transcription factor network. PLoS Comp Biol 3:e198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead H (2003) Sperm whales, social evolution in the ocean. The University of Chicago Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins J, Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Adaptationism and the adaptive landscape. Biol Philos 24:199–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson M, Hanlon R, Tyack P, Madsen PT (2008) Big bang? Intense ultrasound does not have any detectable effects on the squid Loligo pealeii. Bioacoustics 17:321–323

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (2007) Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: piecewise approximations to reality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I have benefitted greatly from comments from, and discussions with, Hanne Andersen, Sabina Leonelli, Arnon Levy, William Bechtel, Fridolin Gross, Samuel Schindler, Maureen O’Malley, and four anonymous reviewers. I would like to thank Peter Madsen, Malcolm Clarke, Paulien Hogeweg, and Uri Alon for inspiration and guidance through their research. This research was undertaken as part of the project Philosophy of Contemporary Science in Practice, funded by the Danish Research Council for Independent Research/Humanities.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sara Green.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Green, S. A Philosophical Evaluation of Adaptationism as a Heuristic Strategy. Acta Biotheor 62, 479–498 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-014-9232-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-014-9232-x

Keywords

Navigation