Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-2lccl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T18:10:46.899Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A “Revolutionary” Philosophy of Science: Feyerabend and The Degeneration of Critical Rationalism Into Sceptical Fallibilism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

John G. McEvoy*
Affiliation:
University of Cincinnati

Extract

The works of Paul K. Feyerabend, Norwood Russell Hanson and Thomas S. Kuhn have come to occupy a central place in the annals of contemporary philosophy of science. Some of their contemporaries, ([1], [14], [20]), tend to regard them as the vanguard of a new “revolutionary” intellectual movement. Reacting against the views of their positivist predecessors, they embrace and propagate the idea that “pervasive presuppositions” are fundamental to scientific investigations. Thus, Feyerabend thinks that, “... scientific theories are ways of looking at the world; and their adoption affects our general beliefs and expectations, and thereby also our experiences and our conception of reality” ([5], p. 29). This is in stark contrast to the positivist view that the aim of science is the systematization of experience that exists independently of any scientific theories ([12], p. 178). This new view of scientific theories also involves a “radical” conception of the nature of theoretical change. Rejecting the positivist notion of any constant element (experience, observation language, etc.) through such change, Kuhn regards a basic theoretical change as a conceptual revolution and “wants to say that after a revolution scientists are responding to a different world” ([14], p. 110). Hanson uses the phrase ‘theory-loaded’ to give expression to a view of the semantic content of observation statements that follows from this general position ([11], pp. 19 ff.).

Type
Discussion
Copyright
Copyright © 1975 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I wish to express my thanks to P. Machamer for his constructive comments on an earlier version of this article and for many helpful discussions on problems relating to the matters therein. I would also like to express my gratitude to L. L. Laudan and G. J. Massey for helpful discussions and comments and to R. Faaborg and W. E. Morris for useful comments and criticisms.

References

REFERENCES

Achinstein, P.On the Meaning of Scientific Terms.” Journal of Philosophy 61 (1964): 497509.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Achinstein, P. Concepts of Science. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press, 1968.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K.An Attempt at a Realistic Interpretation of Experience.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (New Series) LVIII (1958): 143170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K.Explanation, Reduction and Empiricism.” In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. III. Edited by Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1962. Pages 2897.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K.Problems of Empiricism.” In Beyond the Edge of Certainty. Edited by Colodny, R. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 1965. Pages 145150.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K.Comments and Criticism: On the Meaning of Scientific Terms.” Journal of Philosophy 61 (1964): 266274.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K.Reply to Criticism: Comments on Smart, Sellars, and Putnam.” In Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. II. Edited by Cohen, R. S. and Wartofsky, M. W. New York: Humanities Press, 1965. Pages 223261.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K.Problems of Empiricism II.” In The Nature and Function of Scientific Theories.“ Edited by Colodny, R. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1970. Pages 275353.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K.Against Method.” In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. IV. Edited by Radner, M. and Winokur, S. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1970. Pages 17130.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. K.Consolations for the Specialist.” In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Edited by Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. E. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970. Pages 197230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanson, N. R. Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1958.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G.The Theoretician's Dilemma.” In Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: Free Press, 1965. Pages 173226.Google Scholar
Kordig, C. S.The Theory Ladeness of Observation.” Review of Metaphysics XXIV (1971): 448484.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962.Google Scholar
Lakatos, I.Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes.” In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Edited by Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970. Pages 91196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machamer, P.Feyerabend and Galileo: The Interaction of Theories and the Reinterpretation of Experience.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 1 (1973): 146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. R. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York: Basic Books, 1959.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R.The Aim of Science.” Ratio I (1957): 2435.Google Scholar
Putnam, H.How Not to Talk About Meaning.” In Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. II. Edited by Cohen, R. S. and Wartofsky, M. W. New York: Humanities Press, 1965. Pages 205222.Google Scholar
Shapere, D.Meaning and Scientific Change.” In Mind and Cosmos. Edited by Colodny, R. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966.Google Scholar
Schlick, M.The Turning Point in Philosophy.” In Logical Positivism. Edited by Ayer, A. J. New York: Free Press, 1959. Pages 5359.Google Scholar
Schlick, M.The Foundations of Knowledge.” In Logical Positivism. Edited by Ayer, A. J. New York: Free Press, 1959. Pages 209227.Google Scholar
Townsend, B.Feyerabend's Pragmatic Theory of Observation and the Compatibility of Alternative Theories.” In Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. VIII. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1972. Pages 202211.Google Scholar