690
Views
14
CrossRef citations to date
0
Altmetric
Articles

Hume's Experimental Method

Pages 577-599 | Published online: 29 May 2012
 

Abstract

In this article I attempt to reconstruct David Hume's use of the label ‘experimental’ to characterise his method in the Treatise. Although its meaning may strike the present-day reader as unusual, such a reconstruction is possible from the background of eighteenth-century practices and concepts of natural inquiry. As I argue, Hume's inquiries into human nature are experimental not primarily because of the way the empirical data he uses are produced, but because of the way those data are theoretically processed. He seems to follow a method of analysis and synthesis quite similar to the one advertised in Newton's Opticks, which profoundly influenced eighteenth-century natural and moral philosophy. This method brings him much closer to the methods of qualitative, chemical investigations than to mechanical approaches to both nature and human nature.

Notes

1I am indebted for helpful comments and discussion to David Bloor, Márta Fehér, Giora Hon, Brad Hume, Ruth Lorand, Gábor Palló, Jeff Schwegman, Thomas Sturm, Gábor Zemplén and an anonymous referee of the Journal. My research has been supported by OTKA (79193).

2See e.g. Margaret Schabas, The Natural Origins of Economics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005) 80.

3See e.g. Gary Hatfield, ‘Remaking the Science of Mind: Psychology as Natural Science’, in Inventing Human Science, edited by Christopher Fox, Roy Porter and Robert Wokler (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995) 208.

4Reinhard Brandt, ‘Philosophical Methods’, in The Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Philosophy, edited by Knud Haakonssen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006) 143.

5David Allan, Virtue, Learning and the Scottish Enlightenment (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1993) 154.

6See Michael Barfoot, ‘Hume and the Culture of Science’, in Studies in the Philosophy of the Scottish Enlightenment, edited by M. A. Stewart (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990) and Eugene Sapadin, ‘A Note on Newton, Boyle, and Hume's “Experimental Method”', Hume Studies, 23 (1997): 337–344.

7See Paul Wood, ‘The Natural History of Man in the Scottish Enlightenment’, History of Science, 28 (1990): 89–123.

8Peter Hanns Reill, Vitalizing Nature in the Enlightenment (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2005) 37f.

9For a diagrammatic overview see Sachiko Kusukawa, ‘Bacon's Classification of Knowledge’, in The Cambridge Companion to Bacon, edited by Markku Peltonen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996) 69.

10See John Gascoigne, ‘The Study of Nature’, in The Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Philosophy, edited by Knud Haakonssen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006) 863f.

11David Hume's works are quoted from the Clarendon Edition: Treatise of Human Nature (THN), edited by David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007), following the form: book.part.section.paragraph. His Enquiries concerning Human Understanding (EHU), edited by Tom Beauchamp (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000); Enquiries concerning the Principles of Morals (EPM), edited by Tom Beauchamp (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000) are quoted as: section.paragraph.

12Thomas Kuhn, ‘Mathematical versus Experimental Traditions in the Development of Physical Science’, in The Essential Tension (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976) 50.

13Whereas I do not have the space to discuss this problem here, Hume certainly does it in the EHU's chapter ‘Of Miracles’. For a recent discussion of the epistemological relevance of this section see Axel Gelfert, ‘Hume on Testimony Revisited’, Logical Analysis and the History of Philosophy, 13 (2010): 60–75.

14David Hume, ‘Of the Study of History’, in Essays, Moral, Political and Literary, vol. 2., edited by T. H. Green and T. H. Grose (London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1882) 390.

15David Hume, ‘Of the Rise and Progress of the Arts and Sciences’, in Essays, Moral, Political and Literary, vol. 1., edited by T. H. Green and T. H. Grose (London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1882) 175ff.

16Kuhn, op. cit., 44.

17Hatfield, op. cit., 208.

18Wood, op. cit., 98f.

19Roger L. Emerson, ‘Hume's Intellectual Development: Part II’, in Essays on David Hume, Medical Men and the Scottish Enlightenment (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2009) 103–127.

20John Locke, An Essay concerning Human Understanding, edited by Peter Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975) 1.2.9.

21Peter J. Marshall and Glyndwr Williams, The Great Map of Mankind: Perceptions of the New Worlds in the Age of Enlightenment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982) 93.

22David Hume, ‘Of National Characters’, in Essays, Moral, Political and Literary, vol 1., edited by T. H. Green and T. H. Grose (London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1882) 246ff.

23See Thomas Hobbes, ‘Six Lessons to the Savilian Professors of the Mathematics’, in The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, vol. 7, edited by William Molesworth. (London: Longman, Brown, Green and Longmans, 1845) 184.

24See Daniel Garber, ‘Descartes and Method in 1637’, in Descartes Embodied (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000) 37.

26See Isaac Newton, ‘Newton to Cotes. Unsent Draft: Circa March 1713’, in Philosophical Writings, edited by Andrew Janiak (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004) 120f.

25Thomas Sprat, History of the Royal Society (London: J. Martyn and J. Allestry, 1667) 341.

27 Letters of David Hume, vol. 1, edited by J. Y. T. Greig (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1932) 16.

28See Lisa Jardine, Francis Bacon and the Art of Discourse (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1974) 249f. On some limitations of the method Hume proposes in EHU see Thomas Sturm, ‘Freedom and the Human Sciences: Hume’s Science of Man versus Kant’s Pragmatic Anthropology’, Kant Yearbook, 3 (2011): 27–31.

29See Leon Pompa, Human Nature and Historical Knowledge: Hume, Hegel and Vico (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990) 21 and 36f.

30Hume in these passages seems to echo Newton's ‘Rules for the Study of Natural Philosophy’ in Newton, op. cit., 87ff.

31Roger Smith, ‘The Language of Human Nature’, in Inventing Human Science, edited by Christopher Fox, Roy Porter and Robert Wokler (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995) 89.

32Thomas Dixon, From Passions to Emotions: The Creation of a Secular Psychological Category (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003) 107.

33For an overview of the problem see Eric Schliesser, ‘Hume's Newtonianism and Anti-Newtonianism’, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2008 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2008/entries/hume-newton/

34See Isaac Newton, ‘Rules for the Study of Natural Philosophy’, in Newton, op. cit., 87.

35See George E. Smith, ‘The Methodology of the Principia’, in The Cambridge Companion to Newton, edited by I. B. Cohen and George E. Smith (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002) 143.

36See Kuhn, op. cit., 41 and Peter Dear, Discipline and Experience (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995) 242.

37See I. Bernard Cohen, ‘The Case of the Missing Author’, in Isaac Newton's Natural Philosophy, edited by Jed Z. Buchwald and I. Bernard Cohen (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2001) 22f.

38See Márta Fehér, ‘The Method of Analysis-Synthesis and the Structure of Causal Explanation in Newton’, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1 (1986): 60–84.

42Newton, ‘Query 31’, in Newton, op. cit., 139.

39See Jardine, op. cit., 17ff.

40See Russell McCormmach, Speculative Truth: Henry Cavendish, Natural Philosophy, and the Rise of Modern Theoretical Science (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004) 38.

41See Robert E. Schofield, Mechanism and Materialism: British Natural Philosophy in an Age of Reason (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1969) 10 and Deborah A. Redman, The Rise of Political Economy as a Science: Methodology and the Classical Economists (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997), 107.

43Newton, op. cit., 140.

44Newton, ‘Author’s Preface to the Reader, First Edition’, in Newton, op. cit., 41.

45Newton, ‘Query 31’, op. cit., 139.

46See Jaakko Hintikka and Unto Remes, The Method of Analysis (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1974) 110.

47See Garber, op. cit., 37.

48See Hintikka and Remes, op. cit., 106ff and Redman, op. cit., 171ff.

49See A. L. Donovan, Philosophical Chemistry in the Scottish Enlightenment: The Doctrines and Discoveries of William Cullen and Joseph Black (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1975) 96ff.

50See also THN 3.3.6.6 and Letters of David Hume, op. cit., 32f.

51Schofield, op. cit., 95.

52See Schofield, op. cit., 10f and 91ff.

53Reill, op. cit., 69; see also Wood, op. cit.

54Andrew Cunningham, ‘Hume's Vitalism and Its Implications’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 15 (2007): 59–73.

55See Schofield, op. cit., 109.

56See Reill, op. cit., 67ff and Donovan, op. cit., 96f.

Reprints and Corporate Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

To request a reprint or corporate permissions for this article, please click on the relevant link below:

Academic Permissions

Please note: Selecting permissions does not provide access to the full text of the article, please see our help page How do I view content?

Obtain permissions instantly via Rightslink by clicking on the button below:

If you are unable to obtain permissions via Rightslink, please complete and submit this Permissions form. For more information, please visit our Permissions help page.