Skip to main content
Log in

Why do military dictatorships become presidential democracies? Mapping the democratic interests of autocratic regimes

  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent data show that virtually all military dictatorships that democratize become presidential democracies. I hypothesize that the reason is that military interests are able to coordinate on status-preserving institutional change prior to democratization and prefer political institutions with strong veto players. Civilian interests are more likely to suffer from coordination failure by being more diverse and less cohesive, implying that most military democratizations are planned partially while most democratization events from civilian autocracy are unforeseen or poorly planned. Exploring the characteristics of 111 democratization episodes between 1950 and 2017 illustrates features broadly consistent with further theoretical predictions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. An alternative way of categorizing autocracies, popularized by Geddes (1999), consists in distinguishing between personalist, military and single-party regimes. Historically, that distinction has been important in the transition from personalist to hereditary autocracy, and the consequent reduction in conflicts related to succession (Kurrild-Klitgaard 2000; Tullock 2001; Kokkonen and Sundell in press). In the following, most military dictatorships, as categorized by Cheibub et al. (2010) and Bjørnskov and Rode (in press) also would be categorized as military by Geddes (1999), and all communist regimes in the following likewise are single-party. The main difference is that civilian autocracies, in the present category, need not be personalist.

  2. It is worth noting that the same transition appears in all regions of the world—it is thus not a Latin American phenomenon—and regardless of the country’s specific history. Bjørnskov and Rode (in press), for example, show that colonial ancestry (British, French or other colonial history) does not affect coup risks when countries become independent, although it does affect their likelihood of democratizing.

  3. The single case is Peru in the 1990s, when the democratically elected President Alberto Fujimori disregarded the democratic institutions and eventually had to flee the country. After a de facto interim autocratic regime, the constitutional institutions proved robust enough to re-establish democracy without much ado.

  4. In many cases, more than two parties exist or form around democratization. However, the assumption of two parties likely reflects reality when the party system either develops two dominant parties or two approximately coherent blocs of parties (the left and right), as appears to be the case (as documented in the online appendix). When the party system becomes characterized by lax party discipline, as in the United States, it might even form two identifiable groups of politicians across party lines with similar interests on issues of military interest. The assumption of two parties is likely to be problematic only in the case of multiple parties competing in a multi-dimensional issue space, or when the party system develops small pivot parties. Conversely, while an incumbent cannot know prior to democratization the extent to which the parliamentary system develops party discipline, assuming that it does appears to be a rationally conservative choice for both the incumbent government as well as for the present theoretical framework.

  5. A further logical extension of this result is that the incumbent government may have a particular interest in choosing a policy mix that, for example, yields sufficient subsidies to a subset of industries—perhaps best thought of as what was once called the ‘commanding heights’ industries—while achieving the opposite for other industries. That policy mix can, for example, be one in which a subset of industries is protected by high import tariffs while other subsets that potentially could form an alternative majority are exposed to free trade. The mix would reduce their profit margins to the extent that they would have little interest in seeking subsidies—and, thus, represent a threat to the incumbent—because the coordination cost would be prohibitively high relative to the potential gain.

  6. As noted above, in parliamentary systems with multiple parties in which coalitions are necessary to assemble a governing majority, partisan veto players can be effective. However, nothing assures that any constitutional provisions result in either a multiple-party system, a two-party system or a system with dominant parties. As such, presidentialism is the one certain constitutional choice with which to create institutional veto players.

  7. It is worth noting that, theoretically, military competence [as in Eqs. (18) and (19)] may either strengthen or weaken the incentive to democratize, because the net effect depends on the coup risk when not democratizing relative to the risk of losing a democratic election.

  8. An additional result here is that military competence makes it more likely that a presidential system is preferable whenever the condition \(\left( {1 - \mu } \right)\xi m_{0} < \Delta \left( {1 - \theta } \right)\left( {1 - \varphi } \right)m_{p}\) holds, essentially implying the intuitive condition that when the best military spending under autocracy is less than the best possible expected military spending under democracy, a more competent military regime will chose to democratize to a presidential system that minimizes its potential loss.

  9. Conversely, many democratizations from civilian autocracy resulted in new or clearly amended constitutions drafted and introduced after the regime change: 30% introduced a new constitution that was negotiated after democratization. Among military dictatorships, the same pattern has been rare, with only five cases (8%)—Brazil in 1988, the Central African Republic in 1994, Greece in 1975, Poland in 1992 and Venezuela in 1961—in which drafting a new constitution was left to the new regime. The Brazilian case also differs owing to the special nature of the constitutional drafting process in which broad interests within the population were taken into formal account. Indeed, the particular way in which new constitutions were drafted also differs significantly across initially civilian and military regimes: 85% of the new constitutions of democratizing civilian autocracies were drafted by either the legislature or the executive branch, or with heavy influence from either. In military dictatorships that democratized, the drafting process of the more frequent new constitutions tended to be delegated to either a constitutional assembly appointed by the dictatorship or an elected special constitutional legislature assembly. Here, only 44% of the drafting processes included direct influence from either the executive or the legislature.

  10. While it is extremely rare that the president can veto legislation formally, all but one of the military constitutions allow the president to initiate legislation. However, most constitutions also allow the parliament to do so, thereby effectively creating shared competencies. That feature is significantly rarer in democracies initiated by civilian autocracies. Conversely, the president in the former regime type almost never is given the right to dissolve parliament, while that feature is approximately twice as likely to be present in the constitution in the democracies initiated by civilian autocracies.

  11. In addition, it may be worth emphasizing that presidential democracies do not appear more stable than parliamentary types. Although 66% of presidential democracies and only 58% of parliamentary democracies survived the first 10 years after democratization, the difference is far from being significant.

References

  • Acemoglu, D., & Johnson, S. (2006). Economic backwardness in political perspective. American Political Science Review, 100(1), 115–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Acemoglu, D., Naidu, S., Restrepo, P., & Robinson, J. A. (2019). Democracy does cause growth. Journal of Political Economy, 127(1), 47–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, C. (2016). Coup d’état and democracy. Comparative Political Studies, 49(9), 1167–1200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bidner, C., & Francois, P. (2013). The emergence of political accountability. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 128(3), 1397–1448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bjørnskov, C., & Pfaff, K. (2017). The effect of coups d’état on physical integrity rights. Working paper, Aarhus University.

  • Bjørnskov, C., & Rode, M. (in press). Regimes and regime transitions: A new dataset on democracy, coups, and political institutions. Forthcoming in Review of International Organizations.

  • Bjørnskov, C., & Voigt, S. (2018). Why do governments call a state of emergency? On the determinants of using emergency constitutions. European Journal of Political Economy, 54, 110–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blanchard, O. J., & Fischer, S. (1989). Lectures on macroeconomics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boix, C., Miller, M., & Rosatto, S. (2013). A complete dataset of political regimes, 1800–2007. Comparative Political Studies, 46(12), 1523–1554.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M., & Tullock, G. (1962). The calculus of consent: Logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno de Mesquita, B., Smith, A., Siverson, R. M., & Morrow, J. D. (2003). The logic of political survival. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cheibub, J. A., Gandhi, J., & Vreeland, J. R. (2010). Democracy and dictatorship revisited. Public Choice, 143(1–2), 67–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Congleton, R. D. (2010). Perfecting parliament. Constitutional reform, liberalism, and the rise of Western democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Debs, A. (2016). Living by the sword and dying by the sword? Leadership transitions in and out of dictatorships. International Studies Quarterly, 60, 73–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elkins, Z., Ginsburg, T., & Melton, J. (2009). The endurance of national constitutions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Geddes, B. (1999). What do we know about democratization after twenty years? Annual Review of Political Science, 2, 115–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grossman, G. M., & Helpman, E. (1994). Protection for sale. American Economic Review, 84(4), 833–850.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henisz, W. (2017). Political constrains index (PolCon) dataset. University of Pennsylvania; dataset and codebook. Retrieved January 2017, from https://whartonmgmt.wufoo.com/forms/political-constraint-index-polcon-dataset/.

  • Hillman, A. L. (1982). Declining industries and political-support protectionist motives. American Economic Review, 72(5), 1180–1187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ishak, P. W. (2019). Autocratic survival strategies: Does oil make a difference? Peace Economics, Peace Science and Public Policy, 25(2), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kokkonen, A., & Sundell, A. (in press). Leader succession and civil war. Forthcoming in Comparative Political Studies.

  • Kurrild-Klitgaard, P. (2000). The constitutional economics of autocratic succession. Public Choice, 103(1–2), 63–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipset, S. M. (1959). Social requisites of democracy: Economic development and political legitimacy. American Political Science Review, 53(1), 69–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • North, D. (1991). Institutions. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5(1), 97–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • North, D., & Weingast, B. (1989). Constitutions and commitment: The evolution of institutions governing public choice in seventeenth-century England. Journal of Economic History, 49(4), 803–832.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. (1965). The logic of collective action: Public goods and the theory of groups. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. (1982). The rise and decline of nations: Economic growth, stagflation, and social rigidities. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • PARLINE. (2019). Database on national parliaments. Retrieved May 2019, from http://www.ipu.org/parline-e/parlinesearch.asp.

  • Persson, T., & Tabellini, G. (1999). The size and scope of government: Comparative politics with rational politicians. European Economic Review, 43(4–6), 699–735.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persson, T., & Tabellini, G. (2006). Democracy and development: The devil is in the details. American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, 96(5), 319–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Przeworski, A. (1991). Democracy and the market: Political and economic reforms in Eastern Europe and Latin America. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, D. (2017). Democracy by mistake. NBER Working Paper No. w23944.

  • Tullock, G. (1967). The welfare costs of tariffs, monopolies, and theft. Western Economic Journal, 5(3), 224–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (1987). Autocracy. Dordrecht: Klüwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (2001). Monarchies, hereditary and non-hereditary. In W. F. Shugart & L. Razzolini (Eds.), The Elgar companion to public choice (pp. 140–156). Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wintrobe, R. (1990). The tinpot and the totalitarian: An economic theory of dictatorship. American Political Science Review, 84(3), 849–872.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yu, S., & Jong-A-Pin, J. (2016). Political leader survival: Does competence matter? Public Choice, 166(1–2), 113–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Marina Rapp for providing the impetus and some of the first ideas for this paper, and Sascha Becker, Geoffrey Brennan, Michael Dorsch, Stephan Gohmann, Arye Hillman, Jean Lacroix, Martin Rode, Ahmed Skali, participants of the first conference on the Political Economy of Democracy and Dictatorship in Münster (February 2017) and the 10th Australasian Public Choice Conference in Melbourne (December 2017), three anonymous reviewers and the editor (Bill Shughart) for comments on earlier versions. I am also grateful to the Jan Wallander and Tom Hedelius Foundation for generous financial support. Needless to say, all remaining errors are entirely my fault.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Bjørnskov.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary material 1 (DOCX 32 kb)

Appendix: Theory

Appendix: Theory

As a first, normalizing the total supply of inelastic labor at 1, and setting total demand for labor at 1 as in (24), the equilibrium wage rate can be written as (25a), expressed as a function of labor demand in industry n in (23), or the less wieldy expression in (25b). It is easy to see that increasing the subsidy s will reduce the wage rate, w. As it also increases price levels, the overall welfare effect on ordinary citizens is unambiguously negative. At the national level, the effect also is negative because the positive effects on the profits of firms within the K-set cannot outweigh the negative effects for most citizens owing to the adverse effect on overall resource allocation when those firms come to employ too much labor reallocated from more efficient uses.

$$x_{n} = a_{n}^{{\frac{1}{1 - \alpha }}} \left[ {\frac{\alpha }{w}} \right]^{{\frac{\alpha }{1 - \alpha }}}$$
(23)
$$\mathop \sum \limits_{i = 1}^{n} \left[ {\frac{{sa_{i} \alpha \beta }}{{x_{n} w}}} \right]^{{\frac{1}{\alpha \beta }}} = 1$$
(24)
$$w = \frac{{x_{n} }}{\beta }\left[ {\mathop \sum \limits_{i \in K} \left( {sa_{i} } \right)^{{\frac{1}{\alpha \beta }}} + \mathop \sum \limits_{i \notin K} \left( {a_{i} } \right)^{{\frac{1}{\alpha \beta }}} } \right]^{ - \alpha \beta }$$
(25a)
$$w = a_{n} \frac{{\alpha^{\alpha } }}{{\beta^{1 - \alpha } }}\left[ {\mathop \sum \limits_{i \in K} \left( {sa_{i} } \right)^{{\frac{1}{\alpha \beta }}} + \mathop \sum \limits_{i \notin K} \left( {a_{i} } \right)^{{\frac{1}{\alpha \beta }}} } \right]^{{\alpha \beta \left( {\alpha - 1} \right)}}$$
(25b)

Rearranging (5) and (6) and differentiating, it is straightforward to show that the minimum size of the price subsidy, s, that will yield a positive effect on profits in the supported firms, is given by (26). Differentiating, the total effects of the price subsidy s on wages are given by (27). The marginal effect of raising s thus depends both on the relative size of the initial wage and subsidy, but also intuitively on the relative share of total profits—the second fraction—accruing to the supported sectors (the K-set).

$$s > \frac{{\left( {\frac{w}{\alpha \beta }} \right)^{{1 - \alpha \left( {1 - \beta } \right)}} a_{i}^{{\alpha \left( {1 - \beta } \right) - \beta }} }}{{\left( {1 + \alpha \left( {\beta - 1} \right) + {\raise0.7ex\hbox{$1$} \!\mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {1 {\alpha \beta }}}\right.\kern-0pt} \!\lower0.7ex\hbox{${\alpha \beta }$}}} \right)x_{n}^{{\left( {1 - \alpha } \right)\left( {1 - \beta } \right)}} }}$$
(26)
$$\frac{dw}{ds} = - \frac{w}{s}\frac{{\mathop \sum \nolimits_{k \in K} \left( {sa_{i} } \right)^{{\frac{1}{\alpha \beta }}} }}{{\mathop \sum \nolimits_{k \in K} \left( {sa_{i} } \right)^{{\frac{1}{\alpha \beta }}} + \mathop \sum \nolimits_{k \notin K} \left( {a_{i} } \right)^{{\frac{1}{\alpha \beta }}} }}$$
(27)

As such, any development that either affects productivity within a ‘favored’ industry, i.e., one in the subset K, or a development that affects the productivity of all sectors through the wage rate w, will increase the price of buying support from an industrial selectorate. In other words, for any given tax rate, economic development—whether balanced or not—can undermine the rationale for maintaining a civilian autocracy.

For the firm choices, the first-order conditions of Eq. (7) are given by (27)–(30).

$$\mu_{m = } \left( {1 - \mu } \right)\left( {\frac{\chi }{m} - \frac{\beta }{a}} \right)$$
(28)
$$\mu_{s} = \left( {1 - \mu } \right)\left( {\frac{{\left( {1 - \chi } \right)\mathop \sum \nolimits_{k \in K} {\raise0.7ex\hbox{${d\Pi _{k} }$} \!\mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{d\Pi _{k} } {ds}}}\right.\kern-0pt} \!\lower0.7ex\hbox{${ds}$}}}}{{\mathop \sum \nolimits_{k \in K}\Pi _{k} }} - \frac{\beta }{a}} \right)$$
(29)
$$\mu_{r} = \left( {1 - \mu } \right)\frac{\beta }{a}$$
(30)

For the voting outcomes in (13) and (14), total income is irrelevant. Because of the assumption of median voter politics, the income of the median voter is the relevant measure. Expression (31) provides the income of the median voter, given that she receives profits from a firm outside of the K-set. Equation (32) provides the median income for a voter receiving dividends from a firm within of the K-set, i.e., a firm that provides support for a civilian autocracy/party A and thus also receives the price subsidy.

$$y_{m, k \notin K} = w + \frac{{a^{1 + \alpha \beta } \alpha \beta }}{{x_{n}^{\beta } }}w^{ - 1} - \left( {\frac{{a_{i} \alpha \beta }}{{x_{n} }}} \right)^{1 - \alpha \beta } w^{1 - \alpha \beta }$$
(31)
$$y_{m, k \in K} = w + s^{2} \frac{{a^{1 + \alpha \beta } \alpha \beta }}{{x_{n}^{\beta } }}w^{ - 1} - \left( {\frac{{sa_{i} \alpha \beta }}{{x_{n} }}} \right)^{1 - \alpha \beta } w^{1 - \alpha \beta } - c_{i}$$
(32)

The sensitivity of median incomes to raising the subsidy, i.e., of buying direct support from industrial special interests, is given by (33) and (34), where R is defined as the relative share of total profits accruing to the firm associated with the median voter. Equations (33) and (34) represent the relevant sensitivities in the policy decisions in (16) and (17). While the sensitivity of ym is unambiguously negative when the median voter is not associated with a firm in the K-set, the sensitivity when the median voter is so may under specific circumstances become positive. However, as can be seen in (34), that requires a sufficiently large subsidy, s, as well as a profit share R larger than αβ/(1 − αβ).

$$\frac{{dy_{m, k \notin K} }}{ds} = - \frac{{R_{k \notin K} }}{s}\left[ {w + \frac{{a^{1 + \alpha \beta } \alpha \beta }}{{x_{n}^{\beta } }} + \left( {1 - \alpha \beta } \right)\left( {\frac{{a_{i} \alpha \beta }}{{x_{n} }}} \right)^{1 - \alpha \beta } w^{1 - \alpha \beta } } \right]$$
(33)
$$\frac{{dy_{m, k \in K} }}{ds} = \frac{{R_{k \in K} }}{{R_{k \notin K} }}\frac{{dy_{m, k \notin K} }}{ds} + 2\frac{s}{w}\frac{{a^{1 + \alpha \beta } \alpha \beta }}{{x_{n}^{\beta } }} - \left( {1 - \alpha \beta } \right)s^{ - \alpha \beta } \left( {\frac{{a_{i} \alpha \beta }}{{x_{n} }}} \right)^{1 - \alpha \beta } w^{1 - \alpha \beta }$$
(34)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bjørnskov, C. Why do military dictatorships become presidential democracies? Mapping the democratic interests of autocratic regimes. Public Choice 185, 21–43 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00736-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11127-019-00736-x

Keywords

JEL Classifications

Navigation