Skip to main content

All Access Pass: All Guilford journals, $49.95 for 3 months | Click on any article to purchase

Considering Victims' Minds in the Evaluation of Harmful Agents' Moral Standing

Published Online:https://doi.org/10.1521/soco.2021.39.4.489

An agent's moral standing is considered as depending on the agent's mind and their harmfulness toward a victim, but a victim's mind and species may also matter. To examine whether a victim's species (i.e., human or another) and a victim's mind are considered in the judgment of a harmful agent's moral standing, the present study modulated the mental capacities of an imaginary species. Only humans' suffering was considered when the other species' mental capacities were presumed to be low (Study 1), but humans' and the other species' suffering were equally considered when the other species had mental capacities that were presumed to be equivalent to those of humans (Study 2). The results suggest that our judgments of the moral standing of an agent 1) depend not only on the agent's mind but also on the victim's mind and 2) are not human species-oriented but human mind-oriented.

References

  • Akechi H., , Kikuchi Y., , Tojo Y., , Hakarino K., , & Hasegawa T. (2018). Mind perception and moral judgment in autism. Autism Research, 11, 1239–1244. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Barrett H. C., , Bolyanatz A., , Crittenden A. N., , Fessler D. M. T., , Fitzpatrick S., , Gurven M., , … Laurence S. (2016). Small-scale societies exhibit fundamental variation in the role of intentions in moral judgment. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 113, 4688–4693. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Bastian B., , Laham S. M., , Wilson S., , Haslam N., , & Koval P. (2011). Blaming, praising, and protecting our humanity: The implications of everyday dehumanization for judgments of moral status. British Journal of Social Psychology, 50, 469–483. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Bastian B., , Loughnan S., , Haslam N., , & Radke H. R. M. (2012). Don't mind meat? The denial of mind to animals used for human consumption. Personality & Social Psychology Bulletin, 38, 247–256. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Bentham J. (1789). An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. Burns J. H., & Hart H. L. A. (Eds.). Oxford: Clarendon Press (1996). CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Carruthers P. (1992). The animals issue: Moral theory in practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Caviola L., , Everett J. A. C., , & Faber N. S. (2019). The moral standing of animals: Towards a psychology of speciesism. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 16, 1011–1029. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Graham J., , Nosek B. A., , Haidt J., , Iyer R., , Koleva S., , & Ditto P. H. (2011). Mapping the moral domain. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 101, 366–385. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Gray H. M., , Gray K., , & Wegner D. M. (2007). Dimensions of mind perception. Science, 315, 619. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Gray K., , Jenkins A. C., , Heberlein A. S., , & Wegner D. M. (2011). Distortions of mind perception in psychopathology. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 108, 477–479. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Gray K., , & Wegner D. M. (2011). To escape blame, don't be a hero—Be a victim. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 47, 516–519. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Gray K., , Young L., , & Waytz A. (2012). Mind perception is the essence of morality. Psychological Inquiry, 23, 101–124. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Haslam N. (2006). Dehumanization: An integrative review. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 10, 252–264. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Jack A. I., , & Robbins P. (2012). The phenomenal stance revisited. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3, 383–403. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Kant I. (1785). Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten [Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals]. (Gregor M. J., & Timmermann J., Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (2012). Google Scholar
  • Khamitov M., , Rotman J. D., , & Piazza J. (2016). Perceiving the agency of harmful agents: A test of dehumanization versus moral typecasting accounts. Cognition, 146, 33–47. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Knobe J., , & Prinz J. (2008). Intuitions about consciousness: Experimental studies. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7, 67–83. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Malle B. (2019). How many dimensions of mind perception really are there? In Goel A. K., , Seifert C. M., , & Freska C. (Eds.), Proceedings of the 41st Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 2268–2274). Montreal: Cognitive Science Society. Google Scholar
  • Opotow S. (1993). Animals and the scope of justice. Journal of Social Issues, 49, 71–85. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Piazza J., , Landy J. F., , & Goodwin G. P. (2014). Cruel nature: Harmfulness as an important, overlooked dimension in judgments of moral standing. Cognition, 131, 108–124. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Singer P. (1993). Practical ethics (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Google Scholar
  • Sytsma J., , & Machery E. (2012). The two sources of moral standing. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3, 303–324. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Takahashi H., , Ban M., , & Asada M. (2016). Semantic differential scale method can reveal multi-dimensional aspects of mind perception. Frontiers in Psychology, 7, 1717. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
  • Weisman K., , Dweck C. S., , & Markman E. M. (2017). Rethinking people's conceptions of mental life. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 114, 11374–11379. CrossrefGoogle Scholar