Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Defining Species: A Multi-Level Approach

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Acta Biotheoretica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Different concepts define species at the pattern-level grouping of organisms into discrete clusters, the level of the processes operating within and between populations leading to the formation and maintenance of these clusters, or the level of the inner-organismic genetic and molecular mechanisms that contribute to species cohesion or promote speciation. I argue that, unlike single-level approaches, a multi-level framework takes into account the complex sequences of cause-effect reinforcements leading to the formation and maintenance of various patterns, and allows for revisions and refinements of pattern-based characterizations in light of the gradual elucidation of the causes and mechanisms contributing to pattern formation and maintenance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are other ways of classifying species concepts, such as operational versus theoretical (Mayden 1999), prospective versus retrospective (O'Hara 1993), history-based versus character-based (Baum and Donoghue 1995), mechanistic versus historical (Luckow 1995), pattern- versus process-based (Cracraft 1983; Harrison 1998), class versus entity concepts (Reydon 2005).

  2. “An adaptive zone is some part of the resource space together with whatever predation and parasitism occurs on the group considered. It is a part of the environment, as distinct from the way of life of a taxon that may occupy it, and exists independently of any inhabitants it might have” (Van Valen 1976, 234). Only “minimally different” adaptive zones are taken into account in order to ensure that higher taxa do not count as ecological species.

  3. The description of the phenomenon varies from GCSC to PSC/GSC. The patterning captured by PSC/GSC has a temporal component (i.e., phylogeny); in contrast, the patterning captured by GCSC and diagnostic criteria associated with BSC focuses on the spatial/geographical aspect (i.e., diagnosable clusters in sympatry). However, the two are related aspects of the same phenomenon, namely the formation of spatial–temporal discrete clusters among organisms (Avise and Wollenberg 1997).

  4. Hudson and Coyne (2002, 1564) further argue that mechanism considerations are also relevant to genealogical species as well, on the grounds that the coalescence of genes alone does not guarantee that groups remain exclusive when isolated populations are once again able to exchange genes.

  5. Mayden makes a similar argument in reference to EvSC: “the non-operational Evolutionary Species Concept […] should serve as the theoretical concept appropriate for the category Species. As operational concepts, the remaining ideas have been incompatible with one another in their ability to encompass species diversity because each has restrictive criteria as to what qualifies as a species. However, the operational concepts can complement one another and do serve a vital role under the Evolutionary Species Concept as fundamental tools necessary for discovering diversity compatible with the primary theoretical concept” (1999, 95).

  6. Wiley (1978, 20) acknowledges a similar dependance vis-á-vis EvSC: “Separate evolutionary lineages (species) must be reproductively isolated from one another to the extent that this is required for maintaining their separate identities, tendencies, and historical fates.”

  7. Claims that the process-level is best suited to define species [e.g., (Ereshefsky 2010)] can be ruled out for the same reasons.

  8. Examples include the Hertz-Thomson characterization of cathode rays discussed by Achinstein (2001), modern nosological classifications whereby symptomatic descriptions encompass several distinct diseases defined in terms of etiology (main cause) and/or pathology (mechanism of the disease) [e.g., diabetes mellitus (Alberti and Zimmet 1998)], the splitting of the memory phenomenon into more and more specific kinds of memory (Roediger et al. 2002).

References

  • Achinstein P (2001) The book of evidence. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Alberti K, Zimmet P (1998) Definition, diagnosis and classification of diabetes mellitus and its complications. Part 1: diagnosis and classification of diabetes mellitus provisional report of a WHO consultation. Diabet Med 15(7):539–553

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Avise J, Ball R (1990) Principles of genealogical concordance species in concepts and biological taxonomy. Oxf Surv Evolut Biol 7:45–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Avise J, Wollenberg K (1997) Phylogenetics and the origin of species. Proc Natl Acad Sci 94:7748–7755

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayala F, Escalante A (1996) The evolution of human populations: a molecular perspective. Mol Phylogenet Evol 5:188–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baum D, Donoghue M (1995) Choosing among alternative “phylogenetic” species concepts. Syst Bot 20(4):560–573

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baum DA, Shaw KL (1995) Genealogical perspectives on the species problem. In: Hoch PC, Stevenson AG (eds) Experimental and molecular approaches to plant binsystematics. Missouri Botanical Garden, St. Louis, pp 289–303

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlocher S (1999) Host race or species? Allozyme characterization of the ‘flowering dogwood fly’, a member of the rhagoletis pomonella complex. Heredity 83:652–662

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradshaw H, Schemske D (2003) Allele substitution at a flower colour locus produces a pollinator shift in monkeyflowers. Nature 426:176–178

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coyne J (1992) Genetics and speciation. Nature 355:511–515

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coyne J, Orr H (1998) The evolutionary genetics of speciation. Philos Trans Royal Soc B 353:287–305

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coyne J, Orr H (2004) Speciation. Sinauer, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Cracraft J (1983) Species concepts and speciation analysis. Curr Ornithol 1:159–187

    Google Scholar 

  • Cracraft J (1989) Speciation and its ontology: the empirical consequences of alternative species concepts for understanding patterns and processes of differentiation. In: Otte D, Endler JA (eds) Speciation and its consequences. Sinauer, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • de Queiroz K (1998) The general lineage concept of species, species criteria, and the process of speciation. In: Howard DJ, Berlocher SH (eds) Endless forms: species and speciation. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 57–75

    Google Scholar 

  • de Queiroz K (2005) Ernst Mayr and the modern concept of species. Proc Natl Acad Sci 102(1):6600–6607

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Queiroz K (2007) Species concepts and species delimitation. Syst Biol 56(6):879–886

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Queiroz K, Donoghue M (1988) Phylogenetic systematics and the species problem. Cladistics 4:317–338

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T (1935) A critique of the species concept in biology. Philos Sci 2:344–355

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky T (1937) Genetics and the origin of species. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (1992) Eliminative pluralism. Philos Sci 59:671–690

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (2010) What’s wrong with the new biological essentialism. Philos Sci 77:674–685

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Figueroa F, Guünter E, Klein J (1988) MHC polymorphism pre-dating speciation. Nature 335:265–267

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Futuyma DJ (1998) Evolutionary biology, 3rd edn. Sinauer Associates, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Gao F, Bailes E, Robertson DL, Chen Y, Rodenburg CM, Michael SF, Cumminsk LB, Arthur LO, Peeters M, Shaw GM, Sharp PM, Hahn BH (1998) Origin of HIV-1 in the chimpanzee pan troglodytes troglodytes. Nature 397:436–441

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P (1999) Squaring the circle: natural kinds with historical essences. In: Wilson R (ed) Species: New Interdisciplinary Studies. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison R (1998) Linking evolutionary pattern and process: the relevance of species concepts for the study of speciation. In: Howard D, Berlocher S (eds) Endless forms: species and speciation. New York, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Hey J, Kliman R (1993) Population genetics and phylogenetics of DNA sequence variation at multiple loci within the Drosophila melanogaster species complex. Mol Biol Evol 10(4):804–822

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch VM, Olmsted RA, Murphey-Corb M, Purcell RH, Johnson PR (1989) An African primate lentivirus (SIVsm) closely related to HIV-2. Nature 339:389–392

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hudson H, Coyne J (2002) Mathematical consequences of the genealogical species concept. Evolution 56(8):1557–1565

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirkpatrick M, Ravigné V (2002) Speciation by natural and sexual selection: models and experiments. Am Nat 159:S22–S35

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1984) Species. Philos Sci 51:308–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lidén M, Oxelman B (1989) Species—pattern or process? Taxon 38:228–232

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luckow M (1995) Species concepts: assumptions, methods, and applications. Syst Bot 20:589–605

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mallet J (1995) A species sefinition for the modern synthesis. Trends Ecol Evol 10:294–299

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Masly JP, Jones CD, Noor MAF, Locke J, Orr H (2006) Gene transposition as a cause of hybrid sterility in Drosophila. Science 313(5792):1448–1450

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayden RL (1999) Consilience and a hierarchy of species concepts: advances toward closure on the species puzzle. J Nematol 31(2):95–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1963) Animal species and evolution. Belknap Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1969) Principles of systematic zoology. McGraw Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1996) What is a species and what is not? PhilosSci 63:262–277

    Google Scholar 

  • Navarro A, Barton N (2003) Chromosomal speciation and molecular divergence—accelerated evolution in rearranged chromosomes. Science 300:321–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noor M, Feder J (2006) Speciation genetics: evolving approaches. Nat Rev Genet 7(11):851–861

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Hara RJ (1993) Systematic Generalization, Historical Fate and the Species Problem. Syst Biol 42:231–246

    Google Scholar 

  • Orr H, Masly JP, Presgraves DC (2004) Speciation genes. Curr Opin Genet Dev 14(6):675–679

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paterson H (1985) The recognition concept of species. In: Vrba E (ed) Species and speciation. Transvaal Museum, Pretoria

    Google Scholar 

  • Phadnis N, Orr H (2009) A single gene causes both male sterility and segregation distortion in drosophila hybrids. Science 323(5912):376–379

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reydon T (2005) On the nature of the species problem and the four meanings of ‘species’. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 36:135–158

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roediger H, Marsh E, Lee S (2002) Kinds of memory. In: Pashler H, Yantis S, Medin D, Gallistel R, Wixted J (eds) Stevens’ handbook of experimental psychology. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Schilthuizen M (2000) Dualism and conflicts in understanding speciation. BioEssays 22:1134–1141

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schluter D (2009) Evidence for ecological speciation and its alternative. Science 323:737–741

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaw KL (1998) Species and the diversity of natural groups. In: Howard DJ, Berlocher SJ (eds) Endless forms: species and speciation. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 44–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Sneath PHA, Sokal RR (1973) Numerical taxonomy: the principles and practice of numerical classification. W. H. Freeman, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Tajima F (1983) Evolutionary relationship of dna sequences in finite populations. Genetics 105:437–460

    Google Scholar 

  • Templeton A (1989) The meaning of species and speciation: a genetic perspective. In: Otte D, Endler J (eds) Speciation and its consequences. Sinauer, Sunderland, pp 3–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Valen L (1976) Ecological species, multispecies, and oaks. Taxon 25:233–239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiley E (1978) The evolutionary species concept reconsidered. Syst Zool 27:17–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu C (1994) Genetics of postmating reproductive isolation in animals. Annu Rev Genet 28:283–308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yu Q, Colot HV, Kyriacou CP, Hall JC, Rosbash M (1987) Behaviour modification by in vitro mutagenesis of a variable region within the period gene of Drosophila. Nature 326:765–769

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Lindley Darden, Erika Milam, Eric Saidel, Pamela Henson, Joan Straumanis, the DC History and Philosophy of Biology group, as well as three anonymous reviewers and the editor for helpful comments and discussion. This work is supported by ‘Fonds de la recherche sur la société et la culture’, Québec, Canada [grant number 127231].

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tudor M. Baetu.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Baetu, T.M. Defining Species: A Multi-Level Approach. Acta Biotheor 60, 239–255 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-011-9143-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-011-9143-z

Keywords

Navigation