The Wayback Machine - https://web.archive.org/web/20071012144108/http://www.britannica.com:80/ebc/article-65928

Already a member?
LOGIN

Encyclopædia Britannica - the Online Encyclopedia

Search:
Browse: Subjects A to Z The Index
article 176 Shopping


New! 2007 Encyclopædia Britannica Print Set
Revised, updated, and still unrivaled.


2008 Britannica Ultimate DVD/CD-ROM
The world's premier software reference source.


Great Books of the Western World
The greatest written works in one magnificent collection.

Visit Britannica Store

logic, history of

Concise Encyclopedia Article
Print PagePrint ArticleE-mail ArticleCite Article
 Share article with your Readers

Between the time of the Stoics and the revival of logic in 12th-century Europe, the most important logical work was done in the Arab world. Arabic interest in logic lasted from the 9th to the 16th century, although the most important writings were done well before 1300.

Syrian Christian authors in the late 8th century were among the first to introduce Alexandrian scholarship to the Arab world. Through Galen's influence, these authors regarded logic as important to the study of medicine. (This link with medicine continued throughout the history of Arabic logic and, to some extent, later in medieval Europe.) By about 850, at least Porphyry's Isagoge and Aristotle's Categories, De interpretatione, and Prior Analytics had been translated via Syriac into Arabic. Between 830 and 870 the philosopher and scientist al-Kindi (c. 805–873) produced in Baghdad what seem to have been the first Arabic writings on logic that were not translations. But these writings, now lost, were probably mere summaries of others' work.

By the late 9th century, the school of Baghdad was the focus of logic studies in the Arab world. Most of the members of this school were Nestorian or Jacobite Christians, but the Muslim al-Farabi (c. 873–950) wrote important commentaries and other logical works there that influenced all later Arabic logicians. Many of these writings are now lost, but among the topics al-Farabi discussed were future contingents (in the context of Aristotle's De interpretatione, chapter 9), the number and relation of the categories, the relation between logic and grammar, and non-Aristotelian forms of inference. This last topic showed the influence of the Stoics. Al-Farabi, along with Avicenna and Averroës, was among the best logicians the Arab world produced.

By 1050 the school of Baghdad had declined. The 11th century saw very few Arabic logicians, with one distinguished exception: the Persian Ibn Sina, or Avicenna (980–1037), perhaps the most original and important of all Arabic logicians. Avicenna abandoned the practice of writing on logic in commentaries on the works of Aristotle and instead produced independent treatises. He sharply criticized the school of Baghdad for what he regarded as their slavish devotion to Aristotle. Among the topics Avicenna investigated were quantification of the predicates of categorical propositions, the theory of definition and classification, and an original theory of “temporally modalized” syllogistic, in which premises include such modifiers as “at all times,” “at most times,” and “at some time.”

The Persian mystic and theologian al-Ghazali, or Algazel, (1058–1111), followed Avicenna's logic, although he differed sharply from Avicenna in other areas. Al-Ghazali was not a significant logician but is important nonetheless because of his influential defense of the use of logic in theology.

In the 12th century the most important Arab logician was Ibn Rushd, or Averroës (1126–98). Unlike the Persian followers of Avicenna, Averröes worked in Moorish Spain, where he revived the tradition of al-Farabi and the school of Baghdad by writing penetrating commentaries on Aristotle's works, including the logical ones. Such was the stature of these excellent commentaries that, when they were translated into Latin in the 1220s or 1230s, Averroës was often referred to simply as “the Commentator.”

After Averroës, logic declined in western Islam because of the antagonism felt to exist between logic and philosophy on the one hand and Muslim orthodoxy on the other. But in eastern Islam, owing in part to the work of al-Ghazali, logic was not regarded as being so closely linked with philosophy. Instead, it was viewed as a tool that could be profitably used in any field of study, even (as al-Ghazali had done) on behalf of theology against the philosophers. Thus the logical tradition continued in Persia long after it died out in Spain. The 13th century produced a large number of logical writings, but these were mostly unoriginal textbooks and handbooks. After about 1300, logical study was reduced to producing commentaries on these earlier, already derivative handbooks.

Close

Link to this article and share the full text with the readers of your website or blog-post

If you think a reference to this article on history of logic will enhance your website, blog-post, or any other web-content, then feel free to link to this article, and your readers will gain full access to the full article, even if they do not subscribe to our service. You may want to use the HTML code fragment provided below.

To know more about this feature, click here

Copy and paste this code into your page



To cite this page:

1105 Start your free trial
Shop the Britannica Store!