Skip to main content

Towards a Teleonomic Philosophy of Biology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
A Phenomenological Revision of E. E. Harris's Dialectical Holism
  • 171 Accesses

Abstract

The goal of this chapter is to present the dialectical holist stance on key topics in philosophy of biology as a theoretical bridge to Harris’s metaphysics of mind. In Sect. 6.2, I set out Harris’s necessary and sufficient conditions for life and in subsequent sections I compare these contentions with contemporary accounts. The central issues to be discussed in this chapter will be whether the notion of the unifying principle (ϕ) can be applied to the simplest unit of life, and if so, to establish what if any further philosophical insight this provides into the natures of life, evolution, and mind. In Sect. 6.3, I outline Harris’s argument that the explicative process () subsumes and broadens Neo-Darwinism. Here I address whether formal governance in collective living systems provides teleological direction to biological evolution. In the final section, I show that for both Harris and AE, positing formal governance across a range of biological systems implies the Gaia theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Harris purposes that initial emergence of living from the non-living may have been due to a “non-local faster than light influences” akin to the EPR experiment, which at “some threshold in the concrescence of convoluted polymers may have occurred in the primeval seas, which spontaneously initiated the generation and fecundation of living bacteria” (1991, 68). Harris made this appeal to defend his conclusion that living unity is implicit within and necessitated by prior processes of quantum mechanics. Though this line of consideration is beyond the scope of the present thesis, Harris appears to have anticipated what is now a flourishing area of research concerned with the Quantum Aspects of Life (Abbott, et al. 2008).

  2. 2.

    With this assertion, Harris (1991, 64) and later Thompson (2007, 152) follow Hans Jonas (1966), who articulated this very conception of freedom.

  3. 3.

    To this end, Harris follows Rupert Sheldrake’s speculative postulate of the morphogenetic field to be supported by a marriage between chaos and biology (1991, 74). Since the connection of fractal geometry to biology has already demonstrated itself to be a fruitful (e.g. Scott, 2007; Hancock, 2014), Sheldrake’s postulation of a (metaphysical) morphogenetic field appears redundant to the extent that it succeeds and excessively speculative to the extent that it posits as yet unsubstantiated forces in nature.

  4. 4.

    Wolpert (2013) contends embryogenesis is a clear example of an increase in biological complexity over time, but one that reveals why evolution cannot be held responsible. “At best, one might argue that the embryo’s increase in complexity arose via competition occurring in the past, between its ancestors and their antagonists. This is a rather torturous connection between a current rise in complexity of a system and the process of natural selection. It also doesn’t address the possibility of hand-crafting an artificial embryo so that its complexity will rise in an artificial womb, without that womb having any ancestors” (247). In other words, biological self-organization whether of an individual cell or development through ontogenesis is presupposed by natural selection rather than its effect.

  5. 5.

    Towards a metabolism-first model, Davies (2008) considers the “citric-acid cycle” to be one example of an autocatalytic system serving as a self-organizing precursor of living beings, “which forms the basis of intermediary metabolism” (109). Zeravcica and Brennerc (2017) have made great strides towards such a model with their research on soft-matter self-organization involving colloidal spheres.

  6. 6.

    In this vein Ball (2009) has argued extensively that among other phenomena, lightning, convective roll cells, and river networks are structures “that arise because they offer ‘channels’ for relieving energy stress and producing entropy efficiently”. Following a number of predecessors, he goes on to write, “life itself is an example of non-equilibrium regularity and structure”, what he considers one of a number of “inevitable ordered forms, waiting to burst forth as soon as the universe gets the chance” (208). Additionally, see de Duve (2008), in which he considers life as a cosmic imperative.

  7. 7.

    Perunov et al. contend that “an endless variety of far-from-equilibrium many-particle Newtonian systems are capable of exhibiting self-organization phenomena in which strikingly patterned structures emerge in the presence of dissipative external drives” (2016, 23). The types of phenomena they have in mind include sand dunes, snowflakes, hurricanes, spiral bundles of protein filaments, and motors, a list that appears redundant after the above discussion concerning emergence. Indeed, the “nonequilibrium world offers many test cases for the general hypothesis that organized, kinetically stable structures emerge and persist because their formation is reliably accompanied by extra work absorption and dissi-pation” (ibid.).

  8. 8.

    Walker’s (2014) theory is in line with Tononi’s integrated information theory of consciousness. In either case, she holds “Φ quantifies how much information is generated by a physical system when it enters a particular state through the causal interactions among its elements, above and beyond the information generated independently by its parts” (433). I return to this theory in Chap. 8.

  9. 9.

    According to Thompson, whereas an ant colony may be autonomous, it is not autopoietic because the components do not bear a circular causal relationship with its boundary. Similarly, allopoietic systems such as ribosomes or vesicles are not autonomous since they lack this circularity, their end product being different from themselves. Viruses are exemplified as systems that are also non-autonomous because outside of a host, they “do not exchange matter or energy with the environment” and are “completely inert […] subject to the vicissitudes of the environment” (123).

  10. 10.

    Though space prevents my further discussion of the issue, Bohm’s extension of the implicate order to the nature of living systems is largely in agreement with the contentions of this section and the previous. For further details see Bohm (1969).

  11. 11.

    In all his works, we find only one instance in which Harris mentions autopoiesis. He makes reference to Maturana and Varela’s (1980) Autopoiesis and Cognition, to which he remarks that it is by no means new, originating from Aristotle, but that it is certainly in line with his understanding of the irreducibility of an organism. Nevertheless, he finds fault with the theory on account of its being potentially relativistic concerning how such a system makes meaning (2006, 171). For Harris’s nearest anticipation of this theory see (1965, 327-28).

  12. 12.

    Minimal autopoiesis consists only of this maintenance of identity in the circular process of material exchange but it lacks a metabolic network. Autopoiesis plus adaptivity (i.e. active monitoring of internal homeostatic or homeodynamic mechanisms) are required for meaning-making according to Thompson (2007, 148-49). As he further admits, a living material system requires the proactive quality of the latter (e.g. searching for food). To my mind, the former may just as well be considered autocatalytic.

  13. 13.

    Minimal autopoiesis consists only of this maintenance of identity in the circular process of material exchange but it lacks a metabolic network. Autopoiesis plus adaptivity (i.e. active monitoring of internal homeostatic or homeodynamic mechanisms) are required for meaning making according to Thompson (2007, 148-49). As he further admits, a living material system requires the proactive quality of the latter (e.g. searching for food). To my mind, the former may just as well be considered autocatalytic.

  14. 14.

    These include a steady-state inheritance system (consisting of self-regulating and gene-regulating elements), structural inheritance (e.g. cytoskeleton characteristics being passed on through mitosis/meiosis), chromatin marking (e.g. methylation patterns on DNA), and social structures including symbiotic functionality (Thompson, 2007 176-77).

  15. 15.

    Bacteria outnumber human cells 10 to 1 but compose only a few percentages of our body mass, while their number of genes outnumber human genes by 360 times. (http://www.nih.gov/news/health/jun2012/nhgri-13.htm). Hence, the human being is an ecosystem by definition!

  16. 16.

    Lineweaver and Davies (2013) likewise emphasize that information in DNA should be understood as being about its corresponding niches (i.e. like the organism, it is context dependent) and that it has even come from those same niches via natural selection. Davies contends that a gene is “a coded set of instructions for a ribosome to make a protein. Instructional information is clearly more than a mere bit string. There has to be a molecular milieu that can interpret and act on those instructions. In other words, biological information is contextual […] Context is manifestly a global property. You cannot tell by looking at the local level whether this or that base pair in DNA is instructional information or just junk” (Davies, 2013, 33-34). Dehmelt and Bastiaens (2011) provide further sympathetic accounts to this end.

  17. 17.

    For further example, Koonin and Wolf (2009) have found that both Lamarckian and Darwinian views are important and capture different modalities of evolution: “in principle, the backward flow of specific information from the phenotype – or the environment viewed as extended phenotype – to the genome is not impossible owing to the wide spread of reverse transcription and DNA transposition. Highly sophisticated mechanisms are required for this bona fide Lamarckian scenario to work, and in two remarkable cases, the CASS and the piRNA system, such mechanisms have been discovered” (8). Additionally, Sarkies and Miska (2014) have proposed that mobile RNAi may provide short-term adaptation sufficient for the heritability of acquired characteristics (532).

  18. 18.

    Though not emphasized by Harris, it appears to follow from his articulation of “freedom” that as the species or “swarm” increases its specific capacity to alter an environment; over time it establishes a positive selection effect for specific functions in future generations. In this vein, Harris’s position seems to assert that organic systems, both individual and collective, work toward transcending their own environmental and biological constraints by establishing their own. This issue will be further addressed in the following section.

  19. 19.

    Recognizing that his account is counter the central dogma of Neo-Darwinism, Krakauer argues from what appears to be just the kind of “genetic engineering” mentioned above: “DNA is always associated with histone proteins forming the chromatin complex. Histone proteins possess long tails that can be biochemically modified. Changing the chemical environment of the cell leads to changes in the chemical composition of chromatin. Thereby DNA can be secondarily tagged along a repeating structure that is potentially as information-rich as the genome proper, and possesses the benefit of being directly modifiable within a single cell or organismal generation” (239).

  20. 20.

    Recent discoveries by Chen et al. (2017) reveal evidence that the self-organization of viable niches in bacteria, for example, is achieved by “large-scale collective oscillation” that (in agreement with Gleiser above remarks) once again takes the form of “travelling waves” via “symmetry breaking”.

  21. 21.

    Rothschild (2006) concludes her analysis of emergence in biology precisely in line with an interpretation of “natural selection” as formal governance: the “proper locus of natural selection”, or “evolutionary individuals could very well include the individual gene, organism, deme, and species […] Indeed, one could argue for even more levels, such as the level of a tissue or subcellular organelle” (160).

  22. 22.

    Krakauer (2013) draws a similar conclusion concerning his own conception of evolution to be considered below, finding that the “nature” versus “nurture” dichotomy rests upon the false premise that “some traits are fixed whereas others are variable”. He claims that this premise is false “because nothing about a species remains fixed over suitably long periods of time” (242).

  23. 23.

    In complement to this argument of organism-environment coupling, Krakauer has claimed that “there can be no information in the genome that is not already present in the environment”, which implies that evolutionary complexity “is not a property of an individual but a population” (2013, 233).

  24. 24.

    For further discussions on levels of selection see Wilson (2002); Wilson and Wilson (2007); Lloyd (2007); and Serrelli and Gontier (2015).

  25. 25.

    Here Sepkoski claims macroevolution supports Gould’s theory of punctuated equilibrium: exemplified through the case of a mass-extinction, much like the case of a forest fire, space is cleared for new life to emerge.

  26. 26.

    For a further treatment of the role symbiogenesis plays in evolution see Gontier (2015).

  27. 27.

    Estes et al. (2011) argue that perhaps the greatest human influence on ecology has been the widespread elimination of predators across the globe, which has been largely responsible for the mass extinction currently taking place. It is ironic, they point out, that due to the complex web of species interdependencies, “we often cannot unequivocally see the effects of large apex consumers until after they have been lost from an ecosystem, at which point the capacity to restore top-down control has been lost” (302).

  28. 28.

    Li’s (2002) paper provides significant detail concerning how environmental variables are to be modelled such that “a theoretical framework of ecological phase transitions is scientifically viable.

  29. 29.

    Further examples include amino acids, photosynthesis, wings, antifreeze proteins in the northern sea cod Boreogadus saida and Antarctic Dissotichus nawsoni (consisting of repeating threonine, alanine, and proline), sensitivity to long-wavelength green and red visual pigments, and serine protease molecules in bacteria (subtilisin) and vertebrates (trypsin), which have different structures but the same active site (Chela-Flores 2008, 158-59). Interestingly, Schloss (2008) has argued that convergent adaptations such as lungs, gills, guts, kidneys, organelles, and whole-organism branching morphologies create an internal, “three-dimensional” surface area that effectively endow living systems with an additional, “fourth dimension” (ff. 330).

  30. 30.

    Though he does not cite Kurakin or the Gaia theory, Smith (2013) has argued that “phase transitions” provide the appropriate paradigm for understanding the biosphere. He claims some universal patterns of life should be understood as the order parameters of these transitions. As the phase transitions of the biosphere are dynamical rather than equilibrium, he argues (consistent with Bohm and Harris) the “individuality” of living systems that compose it is “derived” and “emergent” from the “core metabolism” of the biosphere (210).

  31. 31.

    For further discussion concerning the connection between symbiosis and Gaia, see Hird’s (2010). In this work she argues that the dependence of environmental activity and regulation upon bacteria through symbiosis and symbiogenesis can be seen as Gaia’s fundamental actants, connecting life and non-living matter in biophysical and “biosocial entanglements”. Hird also provides a lucid historical summary of how the Gaia theory has subsumed the theory of autopoiesis.

Works Cited

  • Abbott, Derek, Davies, Paul C. W., and Pati, Arun K, eds. Quantum Aspects of Life. Singapore: World Scientific Pub, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ball, Philip. Branches. Nature’s Patterns: A Tapestry in Three Parts. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beschta, Robert L, and Ripple, William J. Large Predators and Trophic Cascades in Terrestrial Ecosystems of the Western United States. In Biological Conservation. Elsevier, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, David. Some Remarks on the Notion of Order. In Conrad H. Waddington, ed. Towards a Theoretical Biology, 2 Sketches. (Aldine, Chicago), 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chela-Flores, Julian. “Fitness of the Cosmos for the Origin and Evolution of Life: from Biochemical Fine-Tuning to the Anthropic Principle.” In Barrow, John D., Simon Conway Morris., Stephen J. Freeland., Charles L. Harper Jr, eds. 151-166. Fitness of the Cosmos for Life: Biochemistry and Fine-Tuning. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, C., et al. “Weak Synchronization and Large-Scale Collective Oscillation in Dense Bacterial Suspensions.” In Nature. Springer Pub, 2017.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coffman, James A. “On Causality in Nonlinear Complex Systems: The Developmentalist Perspective.” In Cliff Hooker, ed. Philosophy of Complex Systems. 287-309. The Netherlands, Amsterdam: Elsevier Pub, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crist, Eileen and Rinker, Bruce H. Gaia in Turmoil: Climate Change, Biodepletion, and Earth Ethics in an Age of Crisis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, Paul C.W. “Fitness and the Cosmic Environment.” In Barrow, John D., Simon Conway Morris., Stephen J. Freeland., Charles L. Harper Jr, eds. Fitness of the Cosmos for Life: Biochemistry and FineTuning. 97-113. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, Paul C.W. “Directionality Principles from Cancer to Cosmology.” In Charles H. Lineweaver, Paul C. W. Davies, and Michael Ruse, eds. Complexity and the Arrow of Time. 19-41. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehmelt, Leif and Bastiaens, Philippe “Self-Organization in Cells.” In Hildegard Meyer-Ortmanns., and Stefan Thurner, eds. Principles of Evolution: From the Plank Epoch to Complex Multicellular Life. 219-38. (The Frontiers Collection). Heidelberg, Germany: Springer Pub, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Estes, James A., et al. “Trophic Downgrading of Planet Earth.” In Science. 301-306. vol 333., 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gleiser, Marcelo. “The Three Origins: Cosmos, Life, and Mind.” In John D. Barrow., Paul C.W. Davies., and Charles L. Harper, Jr., eds. Science and Ultimate Reality: Quantum Theory, Cosmology and Complexity. 637-653. Cambridge University Press, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gleiser, Marcelo. “Emergent Spatiotemporal Complexity in Field Theory.” In Charles H. Lineweaver, Paul C. W. Davies, and Michael Ruse, eds. Complexity and the Arrow of Time. 113-131New York: Cambridge University Press, 2013

    Google Scholar 

  • Gontier, Nathalie. Reticulate Evolution: Symbiogenesis, Lateral Gene Transfer, Hybridization and Infectious Heredity. Interdisciplinary Evolutionary Research. Vol 3. Switzerland: Springer Pub, 2015.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grytsay, V.I., and Musatenko, I.V. “The Structure of a Chaos of Strange Attractors Within a Mathematical Model of the Metabolism of a Cell.” In Phys. 677-86. Vol. 58, No, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hancock, Ronald, and Jeon, Kwang W. eds. New Models of the Cell Nucleus: Crowding, Entropic Forces, Phase Separation, and Fractals. Academic Press, 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, Errol E. The foundations of Metaphysics in Science. London: Allen and Unwin Pub, 1965.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, Errol E. Formal, Transcendental and Dialectical Thinking: Logic and Reality. State University of New York Press, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, Errol E. The Reality of Time. Albany NY: State University of New York Press, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, Errol E. Cosmos and Anthropos: A philosophical Interpretation of the Anthropic Cosmological Principle. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press International Inc, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, Errol E. The Restitution of Metaphysics. Amherst New York: Humanity Books, an imprint of Prometheus Books, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, Errol E. Reflections on the Problem of Consciousness. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer Pub, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hird, Myra J “Indifferent Globality: Gaia, Symbiosis and ‘Other Worldliness.’” In Theory, Culture & Society. Vol. 27 (2–3). 54-72. (SAGE, Los Angeles, London, New Delhi, and Singapore), 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, Cliff. “Introduction to Philosophy of Complex Systems Part A: Towards a Framework for Complex Systems.” In Cliff Hooker, ed Philosophy of Complex Systems. 3-90. The Netherlands, Amsterdam: Elsevier Pub, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, Stuart A. Investigations. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, Stuart A. Autonomous Agents. In John D. Barrow., Paul C.W. Davies., and Charles L. Harper, Jr., eds. Science and Ultimate Reality: Quantum Theory, Cosmology and Complexity. 654-666. Cambridge University Press, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, Stuart A. “Evolution Beyond Newton, Darwin, and Entailing Law: The Origin of Complexity in the Evolving Biosphere.” In Charles H. Lineweaver, Paul C. W. Davies, and Michael Ruse, eds. Complexity and the Arrow of Time. 162-190. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koonin Eugene V., and Wolf, YI. “Is evolution Darwinian or/and Lamarckian?” In Biology Direct. 4:42, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krakauer, David. “The Inferential Evolution of Biological Complexity: Forgetting Nature by Learning to Nurture.” In Charles H. Lineweaver, Paul C. W. Davies, and Michael Ruse, eds. 224-245. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurakin, Alexei. “The Self-organizing Fractal Theory as a Universal Discovery Method: The Phenomenon of Life.” In Theoretical Biology and Medical Modelling. 8, 4, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, James G. “Darwinism and Neo-Darwinism.” In Sahotra Sarkar., and Anya Plutynski, eds. Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. 77-98. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Li, Bai-Lian. “A Theoretical Framework of Ecological Phase Transitions for Characterizing TreeGrass Dynamics.” In Acta Biotheoretica. 50, 3. Springer Pub, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, Elizabeth. Units and Levels of Selection. (pp. 44-65) In Sahotra Sarkar., and Anya Plutynski, eds. Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. New York, NY: Cambridge University, Press 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margulis, Lynn. Symbiosis in Cell Evolution. W.H. Freeman, New York, Second, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margulis, Lynn. Symbiotic Planet: A New Look at Evolution. Basic Books, New York, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margulis, Lynn. “Serial Endosymbiotic Theory (SET) and Composite Individuality: Transition from Bacterial to Eukaryotic Genomes.” In Microbiology Today. 172–174. 31, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, Humberto R., and Varela, Francisco. Autopoiesis and Cognition. Boston, MA: Reidel Pub, 1980.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, Humberto R. “Autopoiesis.” In Milan Zeleny ed. Autopoiesis: A theory of the living organization. Westview Press, Boulder, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, Amir. et al. “Adaptive Prediction of Environmental Changes by Microorganisms.” In Nature. Jul 9; 460 (7252): 220-4, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreno, Alvaro, Ruiz-Mirazo, Kepa, and Barandiaran, Xabier. “The Impact of the Paradigm of Complexity on the Foundational Frameworks of Biology and Cognitive Science.” In Cliff Hooker. ed. Philosophy of Complex Systems. 311- 333. The Netherlands, Amsterdam: Elsevier Pub, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman, Stuart A. “Complexity in Organismal Evolution.” In Cliff Hooker, ed. Philosophy of Complex Systems. 335-354. The Netherlands, Amsterdam: Elsevier Pub, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, Jay. “Complex Ecological Systems.” In Cliff Hooker, ed. Philosophy of Complex Systems. 421-439. The Netherlands, Amsterdam: Elsevier Pub, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacock, Kent A. “Symbiosis in Ecology and Evolution.” In Kevin DeLaplante,, Bryson Brown., and Kent A. Peacock, eds. Philosophy of Ecology. 219-250. Amsterdam, The Netherlands. Elsevier, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perunov, Nikolai, Marsland Robert, and England Jeremy. “Statistical Physics of Adaptation.” In Phys. Rev. X. 6, 2, 2016.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothschild, Lynn J. “The Role of Emergence in Biology.” In Philip Clayton., and Davies, Paul C. W., eds. The Re-Emergence of Emergence: The Emergentist Hypothesis from Science to Religion. 151-165. New York. Oxford University Press, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkies, Peter, and Miska, Eric. “A. Small RNAs Break Out: The Molecular Cell Biology of Small RNAs.” In Nature Reviews Molecular Cell Biology, Vol 15. 525-535. Macmillan Publishers Limited, 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schloss, Jeffery P. “Would Venus Evolve on Mars? Bioenergetic Constraints, Allometric Trends, and the Evolution of Life-History Invariants.” In Barrow, John D., Simon Conway Morris., Stephen J. Freeland., Charles L. Harper Jr, eds. Fitness of the Cosmos for Life: Biochemistry and Fine-Tuning. 318-464. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuster, Peter. “Physical Principles of Evolution.” Hildegard Meyer-Ortmanns., and Stefan Thurner, eds. Principles of Evolution: From the Plank Epoch to Complex Multicellular Life. 45-79. (The Frontiers Collection). Heidelberg, Germany: Springer Pub, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, Alwyn C. The Nonlinear Universe: Chaos, Emergence, Life (The Frontiers Collection). Heidelberg Germany: Springer Pub, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sepkoski, David. “Macroevolution.” In Ruse. Michael, ed. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Biology. 211-237. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Serrelli, Emanuele, and Gontier, Nathalie, eds. Macroevolution: Explanation, Interpretation and Evidence. Interdisciplinary Evolution Research. Volume 2. Switzerland: Springer Pub, 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, James A. “Bacteria are Small but not Stupid: Cognition, Natural Genetic Engineering and Sociobacteriology.” In Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci. 807-19. 38, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, James A. Evolution: A View from the 21st Century. Upper Sattle River, NJ: FT Press Science, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Eric. “Emergent Order in Processes: The Interplay of Complexity, Robustness, Correlation, and Hierarchy in the Biosphere.” In Charles H. Lineweaver, Paul C. W. Davies, and Michael Ruse, eds. Complexity and the Arrow of Time. 191-223. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, John. “Foundational Issues in Enaction as a Paradigm for Cognitive Science: From the Origin of Life to Consciousness and Writing.” In John Stewart., Oliver Gapenne., and Ezequiel A. Di Paolo, eds. Enaction: Toward a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science. 1-31. MIT Press, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tabaczek, Mariusz. “The Metaphysics of Downward Causation: Rediscovering the Formal Cause.” In Zygon. 380-404. Vol 48, Issue 2, 28 May, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Evan. Mind in life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, Francisco J., and Goguen, Joseph A. “The Arithmetic of Closure.” In Progress in Cybernetics and Systems Research. 48-63. vol. 3. New York: Wiley Hemisphere, 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, Sara I. “Top-Down Causation and the Rise of Information in the Emergence of Life.” In Information. 424-39. Issue 5, 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, Denis M. “Teleology.” In Michael Ruse ed. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Biology. 113-137. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, David S. Darwin’s Cathedral: Evolution, Religion, and the Nature of Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, David S. and Wilson, Edward O. “Rethinking the theoretical foundation of sociobiology.” In Quarterly Review of Biology, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, D. H. “Information Width: a Way for the Second Law to Increase Complexity.” In Charles H. Lineweaver, Paul C. W. Davies, and Michael Ruse, eds. Complexity and the Arrow of Time. 246-275. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yin, Gao, and Herfel, William. “Constructing Post-Classical Ecosystems Ecology.” In Cliff Hooker, ed. Philosophy of Complex Systems. 389-420 The Netherlands, Amsterdam: Elsevier Pub, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James Schofield .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Schofield, J. (2021). Towards a Teleonomic Philosophy of Biology. In: A Phenomenological Revision of E. E. Harris's Dialectical Holism. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-65029-2_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics