Skip to main content
Log in

Pleasure and Its Contraries

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What is the contrary of pleasure? “Pain” is one common answer. This paper argues that pleasure instead has two natural contraries: unpleasure and hedonic indifference. This view is defended by drawing attention to two often-neglected concepts: the formal relation of polar opposition and the psychological state of hedonic indifference. The existence of mixed feelings, it is argued, does not threaten the contrariety of pleasure and unpleasure.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See e.g. Broad (1959, p. 230), Sidgwick (1981, p. 127), Von Wright (1963, p. 11), Alston (1967, p. 341), Sprigge (1988, p. 128), Johansson (2001, p. 39). Some philosophers prefer to use “enjoyment” instead of “pleasure” in order to refer to that generic concept (Crisp 2006, pp. 101–2). Some others use “happiness”. For Hartmann (1932, vol. 2 p. 160), happiness is opposed to “suffering” and includes “pleasure, satisfaction, joy, blessedness”.

  2. This is meant to be true only for contradiction and contrariety when they operate upon predicables (or properties). That is, the claim is simply that if two predicates (or properties) are contradictory, then they are contraries. It is neither claimed nor entailed that contradictory propositions are contraries propositions. As argued by Geach (1969), thinking of contrariety as an operation applying to propositions might well be mistaken. In accordance with Geach, I shall not rely here on the controversial notion of contrary propositions; only contrary predicables will be appealed to: being pleasant, being unpleasant and being indolent.

  3. To my knowledge, the only attempt to define pain on the basis of pleasure is to be found in Bouillier (1877, Chap. XII).

  4. Barnes’ original definition reads as follows:

    C3(F,G)=(x)((RF=RG) & (Gx Fx)&((H)(((RH=RF) &(H ≠ F) &(H ≠G)) (H is between F and G)))) (Barnes 1969)

    Where “C3”means polar opposition and “R” means the range of a predicate.

    Incidentally, one objection to it runs as follows: F=black, G=white, H=visually extended. It is true that visual extension and color have the same range (whatever is colored is visually extended and whatever is visually extended is colored). It is not the case however that H is between F and G (in any intuitive sense). So according to Barnes’ definition black and white would not be polar opposites (he himself claims that they are). By requiring that H be contrary to both F and G, my definition above avoids this problem.

  5. Aydede (2000) offers a different (though partly overlapping) account of the pain-pleasure contrast.

  6. See also Stumpf (1928, p. 68, n. 1) and Titchener (1908, p. 338 n. 5).

  7. I am here treating obligatory and forbidden, and necessary and impossible, as well as good and bad, as predicates, but the same remarks hold, mutatis mutandis, for the sentential operators ‘it is obligatory/necessary/forbidden … that …’. I intend to remain neutral on the question of whether alethic modalities, norms, and values are better construed in terms of operators or predicates.

  8. A non-arbitrary convention, governed by the behavior of water.

  9. Earlier, Burke (1767, Part I, sect. II) defends indolences against the view that pleasure is the negation of pain alluded to above. Stout (1902, vol. 2 p. 288) grants that there can be indolences, but only after the impression of pleasantness or unpleasantness becomes faint due to habit. Sidgwick (1981, pp. 124–5) defends the existence of indolences, which he refers to as the “hedonistic zero”, but urges that it does not constitute the “normal condition of our consciousness”. Likewise Marshall (1894, pp. 57–8, 244–5) insists that states of indifference are seldom reached: our mental episodes are usually pleasant or unpleasant, but often to such a small degree that we do not notice it.

  10. See Sidgwick (1981, p. 125) for a version of this argument. One version was put forward by Wundt, see Brentano (1995, p. 149).

  11. Stout clearly distinguishes between the question of whether some mental episodes are neither pleasant nor unpleasant from the question of whether our whole mental being, “our total consciousness”, might be neither pleasant nor unpleasant overall. To this latter question he answers negatively.

  12. A distinction introduced, among others, by qualitative hedonists such as Mill (2002, chap. 2); Edwards (1975, 1979.

  13. The view is also called the “bivariate approach”—by contrast to standard “bipolar” approach—and is at the heart of the influential “Evaluative Space Model” of Cacioppo and Bernston (1994).

  14. A view going back to Epicurus:

    Wherever pleasure is present, as long as it is there, pain or distress or their combination is absent. (Epicurus, Key Doctrines, 3–4, in Long and Sedley 1987, vol. 1, p. 115)

  15. Brentano (1979, chap. 3) even argues that in the case of multiple colors, such as orange, the places where the component colors lie (red/yellow) are distinct but too small to be sensorily differentiated (see Massin and Hämmerli 2014, for an assessment of this view).

  16. To the extent that the subjects consciously access the stimuli at stake in these studies, these stimuli might be equated to intentional objects.

  17. I am grateful to an anynymous referee of this journal for having pointed out this issue.

  18. Findlay’s original objection was targeted at hedonic tones theories of pleasure, but is naturally applicable to INDEPENDENCE.

References

  • Alston, W. 1967. Pleasure. In The encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. P. Edwards. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aydede, M. 2000. An analysis of Pleasure vis-a-vis pain. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61: 537–570.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bain, A. 1859. The emotions and the will. London: Joh W. Parker and Son, West Strand.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bain, A. 1875. The emotions and the will. London: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balashov, Y. 1999. Zero-value physical quantities. Synthese 119: 253–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, J. 1969. The law of contradiction. The Philosophical Quarterly 19: 302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, R.F., E. Bratslavsky, C. Finkenauer, and K.D. Vohs. 2001. Bad is stronger than good. Review of General Psychology 5(4): 323–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebe-Center, J. 1965. The psychology of pleasantness and unpleasantness. New York: Russell & Russell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, J. 1996. In An Introduction to the principles of morals and legislation, ed. J. Burns and H. Hart. USA: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, G. 1998. Three dialogues between hylas and philonous (Oxford Philosophical Texts). USA: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bouillier, F. 1877. Du Plaisir et de la Douleur. Hachette et cie.

  • Brentano, F. 1979. Untersuchungen zur Sinnespsychologie. Meiner Verlag.

  • Brentano, F. 1995. Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, L. McAlister, ed. London: Routledge, trad. A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, L. L. McAlister.

  • Broad, C.D. 1959. Five types of ethical theory. Paterson: Littlefield, Adams.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burke, E. 1767. A philosophical enquiry into the origin of our ideas of the sublime and beautiful. London: J. Dodsely.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cacioppo, J.T., and G.G. Berntson. 1994. Relationship between attitudes and evaluative space: A critical review, with emphasis on the separability of positive and negative substrates. Psychological Bulletin 115: 401–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calabi, C. 2011. Emotions et contradictions. In Les Ombres de l’Âme: Penser les émotions négatives, ed. C. Tappolet, F. Teroni, and A. Konzelmann Ziv. Genève: Markus Haller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. 2002. La Construction Logique du Monde. Paris: Vrin, trad. E. Schwartz, T. Rivain.

  • Clark, A. 1993. Sensory qualities. USA: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, R. 2006. Reasons and the good. USA: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cruse, D. 1995. Lexical semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E., and R.A. Emmons. 1984. The independence of positive and negative affect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 47: 1105–1117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duncker, K. 1941. On pleasure, emotion, and striving. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 1: 391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, R.B. 1975. Do pleasures and pains differ qualitatively? The Journal of Value Inquiry 9: 270–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, R. 1979. Pleasures and pains: A theory of qualitative hedonism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, J.D., and T.M. Ostrom. 1971. Cognitive structure of neutral attitudes. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 7(1): 36–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elder, C.L. 1996. Realism and determinable properties. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56: 149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fales, E. 1990. Causation and universals. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. 1997. Utilitarianism, hedonism, and desert: Essays in moral philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Findlay, J. 1961. Values and Intentions. London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fréchette, G. 2013. “Searching for the Self: Early Phenomenological Accounts of Self-Consciousness from Lotze to Scheler”. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, to appear.

  • Geach, P.T. 1969. Contradictories and contraries. Analysis 29: 187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. 1977. The structure of appearance (reprint of the original 3rd ed. 1977 ed.). Boston: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. 1980. Case of mixed feelings: Ambivalence and the logic of emotion. In Explaining emotions, ed. A. Rorty, 223–250. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, W. 1882. In Lectures on metaphysics and logic, vol. 1–4, ed. H.L. Mansel and J. Veitch. Edinburgh: William Blackwood and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, N. 1932. Ethics. 3 vols. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd. New York: The Macmillan Company, Trad. Stanaton Coit.

  • Helmholtz, H.V. 1995. In The facts in perception, ed. D. Cahan. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. 1989. A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 2000. In A treatise of human nature, ed. D. Norton and M. Norton. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johansson, I. 2000. Determinables as universals. The Monist 83: 101–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johansson, I. 2001. Species and dimensions of pleasure. Metaphysica 2: 39–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, W. 1964. Logic: Part 1. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 2006. Anthropology from a pragmatic point of view. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, L. 2006. “Pleasure”. plato.stanford.edu.

  • Kenny, A. 1966. Action, emotion and will. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

  • Klocksiem, J. 2010. “Pleasure, Desire and Oppositeness” Journal of ethics and social philosophy.

  • Kristjansson, K. 2010. The trouble with ambivalent emotions. Philosophy 85(4): 485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Külpe, O. 1895. Outlines of Psychology. Ayer Co Pub.

  • Larsen, J.T., and A.P. McGraw. 2011. Further evidence for mixed emotions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 100: 1095.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larsen, J., A. McGraw, B. Mellers, and J. Cacioppo. 2004. The agony of victory and thrill of defeat: Mixed emotional reactions to disappointing wins and relieving llosses. Psychol Sci 15: 325–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larsen, J.T., C.J. Norris, A.P. McGraw, L.C. Hawkley, and J.T. Cacioppo. 2009. The evaluative space grid: a single-item measure of positivity and negativity. Cognition and Emotion 23: 453–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, A., and K. Lehrer. 1982. Antonymy. Linguistics and Philosophy 5: 483–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipps, T. 1903. Leitfaden der Psychologie, 1st ed. Leipzig: Verlag von Wilhelm Engelmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. 2008. An Essay concerning Human Understanding (Oxford World’s Classics). OUP Oxford.

  • Long, A., and D. Sedley. 1987. The hellenistic philosophers: Translations of the principal sources, with philosophical commentary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lotze, H. 1888. Microcosmus: An essay concerning man and his relation to the world. New York: Scribner & Welford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, H.R. 1889. III: The classification of pleasure and pain. Mind XIV: 511–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, H. 1894. Pain, pleasure and aesthetics. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massin, O. 2011. Joies amères et douces peines. In Les ombres de l’âme, penser les émotions négatives, ed. C. Tappolet, A.F. Teroni, and A. Konzelmann Ziv, 55–70. Genève: Markus Haller.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massin, O. 2013a. The intentionality of pleasures and others feelings, a brentanian approach. In Themes from Brentano, ed. D. Fisette and G. Fréchette, 307–337. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massin, O. 2013b. Determinables and brute similarities. In Johanssonian investigations essays in honour of Ingvar Johansson on his seventieth birthday, ed. C. Svennerlind, J. Almäng, and R. Ingthorsson, 388–420. Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massin, O., and M. Hämmerli. 2014. Mélanges Chromatiques: la théorie brentanienne des couleurs multiples à la loupe. In Vers une philosophie scientifique. Le programme de Brentano, ed. C.-E. Niveleau. Paris: Demopolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mezes, S.E. 1895. Pleasure and pain defined. The Philosophical Review 4: 22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. 1869. In Analysis of the phenomena of the human mind, ed. A. Findlater, A. Bain, G. Grote, and J.S. Mill. London: Longmans, Green, Reader and Dyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. 2002. “Utilitarianism” and “On Liberty”: Including “Essay on Bentham” and Selections from the Writings of Jeremy Bentham and John Austin. Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Mulligan, K. 1991. Colours, corners and complexity: Meinong and wittgenstein on some internal relations. In Existence and explanation: Essays in honor of Karel Lambert, ed. B.C. van Fraassen, B. Skyrms, and W. Spohn, 77–101. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, K. 2009. “Emotion and Value”. Oxford University Press.

  • Plato. 1993. Philebus. Hackett Publishing Co, Inc.

  • Plochmann, G.K. 1950. Some neglected considerations on pleasure and pain. Ethics 61(1): 51–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, S. 2004. Six theses about pleasure. Philosophical Perspectives 18: 247–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. 1958. What is mind? The Journal of Philosophy 55: 5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, J.A. 1979. Affective space is bipolar. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 37(3): 345–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. 1995. The analysis of mind. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, J.A., and J.M. Carroll. 1999. On the bipolarity of positive and negative affect. Psychological Bulletin 125(1): 3–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. 1954. Pleasure. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 28: 135–146.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schimmack, U. 2001. Pleasure, displeasure, and mixed feelings: are semantic opposites mutually exclusive? Cognition & Emotion 15(1): 81–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, M. 1962. Problems of ethics. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick, H. 1981. Methods of ethics. Indianapolis: Hacket Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprigge, T. 1988. The rational foundations of ethics. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stout, G.F. 1902. Analytic psychology. London New York: Sonnenschein Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumpf, C. 1928. Gefühl und Gefühlsempfindung. Leipzig: Verlag von Johann Ambrosis Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tappolet, C. 2005. Ambivalent emotions and the perceptual account of emotions. Analysis 65(3): 229–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Titchener, E. 1908. Lectures on the elementary psychology of feeling and attention. New York: The Macmillan Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Trigg, R. 1970. Pain and emotion. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verri, P. 1781. Discorsi Sull’indole del Piacere e del Dolore, Sulla Felicitae sulla Economia Politic. Milan: Giuseppe Marelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Wright, G. 1963. The varieties of goodness. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, D. 2000. Mood and temperament. New York: The Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, D., and A. Tellegen. 1985. Toward a consensual structure of mood. Psychological Bulletin 98: 219–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wohlgemuth, A. 1917. On the feelings and their neural correlates, with an examination of the nature of pain. British Journal of Psychology 8: 423–476.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. 1969. Predicate ranges. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 30: 259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, P.T. 1918. An experimental study of mixed feelings. The American Journal of Psychology 29: 237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am very grateful to Cain Todd, Otto Bruun, Nicole Osborne, Fabrice Teroni, Anne Meylan, Julien Deonna, Guillaume Fréchette, Wlodek Rabinowicz, Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen, Michael Zimmerman, Kevin Mulligan and to two anonymous referees of this journal for their invaluable comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Olivier Massin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Massin, O. Pleasure and Its Contraries. Rev.Phil.Psych. 5, 15–40 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-014-0179-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-014-0179-2

Keywords

Navigation