Skip to main content
Log in

The Biosemiotic Concept of the Species

  • Review Article
  • Published:
Biosemiotics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Any biological species of biparental organisms necessarily includes, and is fundamentally dependent on, sign processes between individuals. In this case, the natural category of the species is based on family resemblances (in the Wittgensteinian sense), which is why a species is not a natural kind. We describe the mechanism that generates the family resemblance. An individual recognition window and biparental reproduction almost suffice as conditions to produce species naturally. This is due to assortativity of mating which is not based on certain individual traits, but on the difference between individuals. The biosemiotic model described here explains what holds a species together. It also implies that boundaries of a species are fundamentally fuzzy, and that character displacement occurs in case of sympatry. Speciation is a special case of discretisation that is an inevitable result of any communication system in work. The biosemiotic mechanism provides the conditions and communicative restrictions for the origin and persistence of diversity in the realm of living (communicative and semiotic) systems.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. That is, no single diagnostic trait can characterise all individuals of the category. Also, common origin is not obligatory for the category; thus, polyphyly is possible.

  2. The concept of family resemblance itself was known long before Wittgenstein; for instance, it was defined precisely by Dugald Stewart already in 1818 (see a review in Mizak 2005).

  3. Krzeszowski (1990: 215–216) writes: „natural categories, characterized by lack of clear-cut category boundaries (fuzziness, ability to stretch), […] permeate natural languages. […] Classical phonology was incapable of handling the well-known phenomenon of phonemic overlap, which involves situations in which many non-prototypical variants of some phonemes belong to a given category because of family resemblance […].“

  4. At the same time, we still retain the assumption that every organism belongs to some genus, familia, and other upper taxa — because (differently from the species) we do not assume that these taxa have been produced and delimited by the organisms themselves.

  5. This is equivalent to the absence of natural selection, the latter being defined as the differential reproduction of genotypes (see also Kull 2014).

  6. Therefore this mechanism is not the one of stabilising selection. In case of stabilising selection, the lower fitness of extreme specimen is due to their particular genotypes, not due to their difference from the average.

  7. Some aspects of this model were described in Kull 1988a, 1993; Lambert and Spencer 1995; Schult 1992; a computer simulation was presented in Kull 1988b.

  8. In many cases, however, we can observe a “double assortativity” (or multi-stage recognition), which means that the recognition of a mate has (at least) two stages — the first, which restricts the range of potential mates (a wider “window”), and the second, where the more detailed comparison (fitting) of the (usually sexual) characteristics of the mates takes place (a narrower “window”); this is obviously a factor that allows the coexistence of close species.

  9. See also the critique of the isolationist concept of species in Paterson (1993).

  10. Thus it is not the same as the Wallace effect, either. See Pfennig and Pfennig (2010); they mention that E. Mayr did not make a clear distinction between character displacement and character divergence.

  11. The importance of Wilhelm Petersen’s work was also noticed by Ernst Mayr (1963: 89; 1999: 209, 255), and by Hugh Paterson (1993: 21).

  12. W. Petersen would belong to Romanes’ tradition, while K. Jordan, who argued against W. Petersen, to the tradition of Wagner.

References

  • Blevins, J., & Wedel, A. (2009). Inhibited sound change: an evolutionary approach to lexical competition. Diachronica, 26(2), 143–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, W. L., & Wilson, E. O. (1956). Character displacement. Systematic Zoology, 5, 49–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky, T., Ayala, F. J., Stebbins, G. L., & Valentine, J. W. (1977). Evolution. San Francisco: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Queiroz, K. (2007). Species concepts and species delimitation. Systematic Biology, 56(6), 879–886.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. T. (1997). Metaphysics and the origin of species. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorelick, R., & Heng, H. H. Q. (2011). Sex reduces genetic variation: A multidisciplinary review. Evolution, 65, 1088–1098.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Grant, P. R., & Grant, B. R. (1989). Sympatric speciation and Darwin’s finches. In: Otte and Endler 1989: 433–457.

  • Grant, P. R., & Grant, B. R. (1997). Hybridization, sexual imprinting, and mate choice. American Naturalist, 149, 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grant, B. R., & Grant, P. R. (2010). Songs of Darwin’s finches diverge when a new species enters the community: implications for speciation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 107(47), 20156–20163.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Gyllenberg, M., Hemminki, J., & Tammaru, T. (1999). Allee effects can both conserve and create spatial heterogeneity in population densities. Theoretical Population Biology, 56, 231–242.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Konuma, J., & Chiba, S. (2007). Ecological character displacement caused by reproductive interference. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 247(2), 354–364.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Krementsov, N. L. (1994). Dobzhansky and Russian entomology: The origin of his ideas on species and speciation. In M. B. Adams (Ed.), The evolution of Theodosius Dobzhansky: Essays on his life and thought in Russia and America (pp. 31–48). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krzeszowski, T. P. (1990). Contrasting languages: The scope of contrastive linguistics. (Trends in linguistics: studies and monographs 51.). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K. (1988a). The origin of species: A new view. In K. Kull & T. Tiivel (Eds.), Lectures in theoretical biology (pp. 73–77). Tallinn: Valgus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K. (1988b). Vidovaya differentsiatsiya kak rezul’tat biparental’nogo razmnozheniya [Species differentiation as a result of biparental reproduction]. In T. Sutt (Ed.), Aktual’nye voprosy evolyutsionnoj biologii [Current problems in evolutionary biology] (pp. 35–45). Tartu: ZBI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K. (1993). Recognition concept of species and a mechanism of speciation. Folia Baeriana, 6, 133–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K. (2014). Adaptive evolution without natural selection. Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 112(2), 287–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kunz, W. (2012). Do species exist? Principles of taxonomic classification. Wiley: Weinheim.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lambert, D. M., & Spencer, H. G. (Eds.). (1995). Speciation and the recognition concept: Theory and application. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mallet, J. (2013). Darwin and species. In M. Ruse (Ed.), The Cambridge encyclopedia of Darwin and evolutionary thought (pp. 109–115). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1963). Animal species and evolution. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1999) [1942]. Systematics and the origin of species from the viewpoint of a zoologist. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Mizak, M. (2005). Why Wittgenstein? Family resemblances. Lingua ac Communitas, 15, 51–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Otte, D., & Endler, J. A. (Eds.). (1989). Speciation and its consequences. Sunderland: Sinauer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paterson, H. E. H. (1993). Evolution and the recognition concept of species. (McEvey, S. F., Ed.). Baltimore: The J. Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pavlinov, I. Y. (Ed.). (2013). The species problem – ongoing issues. Rijeka: InTech.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petersen, W. (1903). Entstehung der Arten durch physiologische Isolierung. Biologisches Centralblatt, 23, 468–477.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petersen, W. (1905a). Ueber die Bedeutung der Generationsorgane für die Entstehung der Arten. In M. Bedot (Ed.), Compte-rendu des séances du sixième Congrès international de zoologie, tenu à Berne du 14 au 16 août 1904 (pp. 213–224). Genève: Imprimerie W. Kündig & Fils.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petersen, W. (1905b). Über beginnende Art-Divergenz (Hadena adusta Esp. — Lepidopt.). Archiv für Rassen- und Gesellschaftsbiologie, 2, 641–662.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfennig, D. W., & Pfennig, K. S. (2010). Character displacement and the origins of diversity. American Naturalist, 176(supplement), s26–s44.

  • Pigliucci, M. (2003). Species as family resemblance concepts: the (dis-)solution of the species problem? BioEssays, 25(6), 596–602.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Rieseberg, L. H., Wood, T. E., & Baack, E. J. (2006). The nature of plant species. Nature, 440(7083), 524–527.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Schult, J. (1992). Species, signs, and intentionality. In T. A. Sebeok & J. Umiker-Sebeok (Eds.), Biosemiotics: The Semiotic Web 1991 (pp. 317–332). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stamos, D. N. (2003). The species problem: Biological species, ontology, and the metaphysics of biology. Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tammaru, T. (1993a). Wilhelm Petersen as a biologist-theoretician. In K. Kull & T. Tiivel (Eds.), Lectures in theoretical biology: The second stage (pp. 122–128). Tallinn: Estonian Academy of Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tammaru, T. (1993b). Biparentality as a creator of non-uniformity in temporal structure of a population. Folia Baeriana, 6, 158–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, J. S. (2009). Species: A history of the idea. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (Ed.). (1999). Species: New interdisciplinary essays. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Hugh Paterson and the late John Maynard Smith for inspiring discussions, and Ene-Reet Soovik and Timo Maran for technical help. The work is related to IUT2-44.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kalevi Kull.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kull, K. The Biosemiotic Concept of the Species. Biosemiotics 9, 61–71 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-016-9259-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-016-9259-2

Keywords

Navigation